Critias:
‘Well (Alla mentoi), I’m saying that
it is not the man who doesn’t do good things but does bad who is
self-controlled (ton mê agatha alla kaka
poiounta ou phêmi sôphronein), but that it is the man who does good
things (ton de agatha) and not bad (all mê kaka) who is (sôphronein). That is, I define sôphrosunê [D.W. ‘self-control] quite
plainly as doing good things (tên gar
tôn agathôn praxin sôphrosunên einai saphôs soi diorizomai).’ –
Socrates: ‘There’s probably no reason why that shouldn’t be true (Kai ouden ge se isôs kôluei alêthê
legein). However, I am surprised (tode
ge mentoi thaumazô) that you believe that men who are self-controlled do
not know that they are self-controlled (ei
sôphronountas anthrôpous hêgê̢ su agnoein hoti sôphronousin)’.’ – Cr.
‘But I don’t (All’ ouch hêgoumai).’
– S. ‘Weren’t you saying a short while ago (Ouk
oligon proteron elegeto hupo sou) that there was no reason why craftsmen
shouldn’t be self-controlled, even when making other people’s things (hoti tous dêmiourgous ouden kôluei kai au
ta tôn allôn poiountas sôphronein)?’ – Cr. ‘I was (Elegeto gar), but what of it (alla
ti touto;)?’ – S. Nothing (Ouden).
But tell me whether you think that a doctor (alla lege ei dokei tis soi iatros), when making someone healthy (huguia tina poiôn), does what is
beneficial not only to himself but also to the man he is curing (ôphelima kai heautô̢ poiein kai ekeinô̢
hon iô̢to;)?’ – Cr. ‘I do (Emoige).’ – S. ‘Is the man who does that doing what
he should (Oukoun ta deonta prattei ho ge
tauta prattôn;)?’ – Cr. ‘Yes (Nai).’
– S. ‘Isn’t the man who does what he should self-controlled (Ho ta deonta prattôn ou sôphronei;)?’
– Cr. ‘He certainly is (Sôphronei men
oun).’ – S. ‘Then must a doctor know (ê oun kai gignôskein anankê tô̢ iatrô̢) when his curing is
beneficial (hotan te ôphelimôs iatai)
and when it’s not (kai hotan mê;)?
Must every craftsman know (kai hekastô̢
tôn dêmiourgôn) when he’s likely to profit (hotan mellê̢ onêsesthai) from whatever work he does (apo tou ergou hou an prattê̢) and when
he’s not (kai hotan mê;)?’ – Cr.
Perhaps not (Isôs ou).’ – S. ‘So
sometimes (Eniote ara) the doctor
does something beneficial or harmful (ôphelimôs
praxas ê blaberôs ho iatros) without knowing which he has done (ou gignôskei heauton hôs epraxen). And
yet, according to what you say, in doing what is beneficial, he has done what
is self-controlled (kaitoi ôphelimôs praxas,
hôs ho soi logos, sôphronôs epraxen). Wasn’t that your point (ouch houtôs eleges;)? – Cr. ‘Yes, it
was (Egôge).’ – S. ‘Then it would
appear that sometimes (Oukoun, hôs
eoiken), when he does what is beneficial (ôphelimôs praxas), he does what is self-controlled (prattei men sôphronôs kai sôphronei),
though he does not know (agnoei d’
heauton) that he is being self-controlled (hoti sôphronei)? – Cr. ‘But that could never happen, Socrates (Alla touto men, ô Sôkrates, ouk an pote
genoito). Still (all’), if you
think that that must follow as a result of what I admitted earlier (ei ti su oiei ek tôn emprosthen hup’ emou
hômologêmenôn eis touto anankaion einai sumbainein), I’d rather retract
part of that admission (ekeinôn an ti
egôge mallon anatheimên) – and I’d not be ashamed (kai ouk an aischuntheiên) to say that I was wrong (mê ouchi orthôs phanai eirêkenai) –
than ever allow that a man who does not know himself is self-controlled (mallon ê pote sunchôrêsaim’ an agnoounta auton
heauton anthrôpon sôphronein).’ (163e8-164d3)
Donald Watt
writes in the introductory note to this section: ‘Socrates … turns to the
question of whether it is possible for the self-controlled man to be ignorant
of his being self-controlled. His argument is as follows: (i) self-control is
doing what one should; (ii) doing what one should is doing good; therefore, by
implication, (iii) self-control is doing
good; but (iv) one may do good without knowing it; therefore (v) one may be
self-controlled without knowing it. Critias consequently abandons this line of
argument. The implication of this section, of course, is that self-control is
doing good knowingly: self-control is the knowledge of (the doing of) the good.’
(Plato, Early Socratic Dialogues,
Penguin Books, 1987, p. 190.)
If Watt is
right, then Plato accomplished a remarkable developmental journey from the Charmides to the Republic, for in the former both Socrates and Critias assume that
craftsmen (tous dêmiourgous) can be ‘self-controlled’
(sôphronein), which on Watt’s
interpretation means that those of them, who are self-controlled, have ‘the
knowledge of (the doing of) the good’. But in the Republic ‘the Form of the good is the highest knowledge’ (hê tou agathou idea megiston mathêma,
505a2), which can be acquired only by true philosophers; it is this knowledge
that entitles them to rule. But is Watt right? In my view, he misconstrued the
argument.
Critias
defined sôphrosunê as ‘doing good
things’ (tên tôn agathôn praxin,
163e10-11). Socrates then asked whether a doctor must know (ê oun kai gignôskein anankê tô̢ iatrô̢)
when his curing is beneficial (hotan te
ôphelimôs iatai) and when it’s not (kai
hotan mê), and every craftsman (kai
hekastô̢ tôn dêmiourgôn) when he’s likely to profit (hotan mellê̢ onêsesthai) from whatever
work he does (apo tou ergou hou an
prattê̢) and when he’s not (kai
hotan mê,164b7-9). When Critias admitted that there was no such necessity
(Isôs ou, 164b10), Socrates
concluded that ‘sometimes (Eniote ara)
the doctor does something beneficial or harmful (ôphelimôs praxas ê blaberôs ho iatros) without knowing which he
has done (ou gignôskei heauton hôs
epraxen, 164b11-c1)’, which means that ‘sometimes, when he does what is
beneficial (ôphelimôs praxas), he
does what is self-controlled (prattei men
sôphronôs kai sôphronei), though he does not know (agnoei d’ heauton) that he is being self-controlled (hoti sôphronei, 164c5-6).’
This Critias
cannot accept, for in his view self-reflection is a necessary constituent of sôphrosunê.
It may be
argued, in support of Watt’s interpretation, that in my abbreviated version of
the argument I omitted Socrates’ introduction of ‘doing what one should’ (ta deonta prattein). The fact is that
Socrates’ two questions concerning this point, and Critias’ responses to them, which
I marked with the bold script, can be taken away without any detriment to the
argument, which consists in Socrates’ refutation of Critias’ definition of sôphrosunê as ‘doing good things’. It
does not mean that the definition of sôphrosunê
as ‘doing what one should’ is otiose within the framework of the dialogue, for
it harks back to the definition of sôphrosunê
as ‘doing one’s own business’ (to ta
heautou prattein), clarifying it without losing the self-reflection implied in ‘one’s own’ (ta heautou):
any doctor and any craftsman who does what he should do, knows that he should do it.
Why is this important
definition brought in by Socrates, yet left without being discussed? Consider Socrates’ investigative
not-knowing, to which all the other definitions of sôphrosunê in the dialogue fall prey, on the one hand, and on
the other hand the closing section, in which Charmides does not accept Socrates’
self-professed ignorance, resolves to be ‘charmed’ by Socrates day by day, Critias
concurs with his resolve, and Socrates complies with it.
No comments:
Post a Comment