Richard
Sorabji wrote to me on December 31, 1980: ‘I have read ‘Socrates in the Phaedrus’ with the greatest pleasure and
interest … I do think your comparisons with Aristophanes are extremely valuable
… May I, however, urge that you separate these important researches from any
connexion with Diogenes Laertius’ claim that the Phaedrus was Plato’s earliest writing? Like Hackforth and the many
people he names, I cannot at present view this even as a serious possibility,
although I have many more reasons than Hackforth records. My reasons have to do
with the central philosophical doctrines of the Phaedrus … I did not feel that I could attach any importance to
Diogenes Laertius’ claim, until someone considered what it would mean for the
central philosophical doctrines … I realise that you do not intend to argue for
Diogenes’ claim but ‘only to see what it would say about the Phaedrus’. But part of this task would
have to be seeing what it said about the central philosophical doctrines … I
don’t know of anyone who has yet undertaken to show this.’
The point
Richard Sorabji makes concerning ‘the central philosophical doctrines of the Phaedrus’ is important.
Socrates’
assertion that ‘if the victory be won by the higher elements of mind guiding
them [the lover and his beloved] into the ordered rule of the philosophic life
(ean men dȇ oun eis tetagmenȇn te diaitan kai philosophian nikȇsȇi ta beltiȏ tȇs dianoias agagonta), their days on earth will be
blessed with happiness and concord (makarion
men kai homonoȇtikon ton enthade bion
diagousin, 256a7-b1, tr. Hackforth)’ is central to the Phaedrus. In the light of this assertion, Socrates refers to
Polemarchus as a man turned to philosophy (epi
philosophian tetraptai), and as such worth emulating (257b).
Polemarchus was
executed by the Thirty Tyrants in 404. The question is, whether after his death,
the unsavoury circumstances of which were widely publicised by Polemarchus’ bother
Lysias in his speech Against Eratosthenes
(one of the Thirty), Plato could see him and present him to his readers as a
man guided by philosophy, a man whose days on earth were therefore blessed with
happiness.
For the
answer to this question we must go to Plato’s Republic, which as a discussion took place in the house of Polemarchus.
If the dialogue was written before the death of Polemarchus, we may expect that
his death profoundly affected Plato’s view of him, and that his presentation of
him in this dialogue gave him an opportunity to retract his Phaedran view of
him. But if it was written after the Republic,
as ‘Hackforth and the many people he names’, and Richard Sorabji, suppose, then
we may expect to find in the Republic
a view of Polemarchus that prompted Plato to present him in the Phaedrus as a man turned to philosophy,
or at least allowed him to do so.
Socrates
opens the dialogue by narrating how he and Glaucon were returning to the city
from Piraeus: ‘Polemarchus the son of Cephalus chanced to catch sight of us
from a distance when we started on our way home (katidȏn oun porrȏthen hȇmas
oikade hȏrmȇmenous Polemarchus ho Kephalou) and told his servant to run and bid
us wait for him (ekeleuse dramonta ton
paida perimeinai he keleusai) … and in a few minutes (kai oligȏ husteron) Polemarchus appeared (ho te Polemarchos hȇke) …
Polemarchus said to me: “I perceive, Socrates, that you and your companion are
already on your way back to the city (Ȏ Sȏkrates, dokeite moi pros astu hȏrmȇsthai
hȏs apiontes).” – Socrates: “You are not far wrong (Ou gar kakȏs doxazeis).” – Polemarchus: “But do you see (Horais oun), how many we are (hȇmas, hosoi esmen;)?” – Soc. “Of course (Pȏs gar ou;).” – Pol. “And are you stronger than
all of these (Ê toinun toutȏn kreittous genesthe)? for if not, you will have to remain where you are (ȇ menet’ autou).”
– Soc. “May there not be the alternative (Oukoun
eti hen leipetai), that we may persuade you (to ȇn peisȏmen humas) to let us go (hȏs chrȇ hȇmas apheinai;)?” – Pol. “But can you persuade us (Ê kai dunaisth’ an peisai), if we refuse to listen to you (mȇ akouontas)?” – Glaucon: “Certainly not (Oudamȏs).” – Pol. “Then we are not going to
listen (Hȏs toinun mȇ akousomenȏn); of that
you may be assured (houtȏ dianoeisthe).”’
(327b2-c14, tr. Jowett).
Am I overinterpreting,
if I see here Plato introducing Polemarchus as a man used to command and not as
a philosopher used to listen to argument and to respond to it? Polemarchus
after all suggests a supper (deipnon)
and then seeing a festival (kai tȇn pannuchida theasometha): ‘there will be a gathering of young men (kai sunesometha te pollois tȏn neȏn autothi),
and we will have a good talk (kai
dialexometha). Stay then (alla menete),
and do not be perverse (kai mȇ allȏs poieite)’ –
Glaucon: ‘I suppose (Eoiken), if you
insist, we must (meneteon einai).’ –
Socrates: ‘Let us do so, if you wish (All’
ei dokei, meneteon einai).’ (328a8-b3, tr. Jowett)
Socrates responds
positively to Glaucon’s desire to stay, not to Polemarchus’ insistence. Is this
of any significance?
I shall
leave the discussion that takes place in the house of Polemarchus, in which
Polemarchus’ father Cephalus and Polemarchus figure as Socrates’ interlocutors,
for my next post.
No comments:
Post a Comment