There are
two passages in Republic III that
elucidate Polemarchus’ performance in Republic
I and in the Phaedrus. The first is
as follows: ‘As for the man of orderly
life (Ho men moi dokei metrios anȇr), when the time comes to describe some saying
or action of another good man (epeidan
aphikȇtai en tȇi diȇgȇsei epi lexin tina ȇ praxin andros agathou), – I think he will be willing to personate him (ethelȇsein hȏs autos ȏn ekeinos apangellein) … But when he comes to a
character which is unworthy of him (hotan
de gignȇtai kata tina heautou anaxion), he will not
seriously assume the likeness of his inferior (ouk ethelȇsein spoudȇi apeikazein heauton tȏi cheironi),
and will do so, if at all, for a moment
only (ei mȇ kata brachu) when he is performing some good action
(hotan ti chrȇston poiȇi).’ (396c5-d5, tr. Jowett)
Polemarchus’
discussion on justice in Republic I
comprises in its totality slightly less than four and a half Stephanus pages,
from 331d4 to 336a8. In comparison, the discussion with the sophist
Thrasymachus takes eighteen Stephanus pages, from 336b1-354a11, and the
discussion of Socrates with Plato’s brothers Adeimantus and Glaucon takes 264
Stephanus pages, from 357a1 to 621d3.
Polemarchus
in that short discussion does, or rather Socrates compels him to do, something
good: he gives up his and his father’s concept of justice.
This first
passage elucidates Polemarchus’ position in the Phaedrus only indirectly, it indicates that when Plato wrote the
dialogue, he was mistaken about him.
The second
passage sheds light on the mistake Plato made in the Phaedrus. Speaking of how to choose the best physicians and judges,
Socrates says: ‘Now the most skilful physicians will be those (Iatroi men deinotatoi an genointo) who,
from their youth (ei ek paidȏn arxamenoi),
besides learning their art (pros tȏi
manthanein tȇn technȇn), have had an extensive acquaintance with disease in
its direst forms (hȏs pleistois
te kai ponȇrotatois sȏmasin homilȇseian); and who, instead of having a
flawless constitution, have themselves suffered from all manners of diseases (kai autoi pasas nosous kamoien kai eien mȇ panu hugieinoi phusei) … But with the judge it is otherwise (Dikastȇs de ge), since he governs mind by mind (psuchȇi psuchȇs archei); he
ought not therefore be to have been trained among vicious minds, and to have
associated with them from youth upwards (hȇi ouk
enchȏrei ek neas en ponȇrais psuchais tethraphthai te kai hȏmilȇkenai), and to have gone through the hole
calendar of crime (kai panta adikȇmata autȇn ȇdikȇkuian diexelȇluthenai),
only in order that he may quickly infer the crimes of others as he might their
bodily diseases from his own self-consciousness (hȏste oxeȏs aph’ hautȇs tekmairesthai ta tȏn
allȏn adikȇmata hoion kata sȏma nosous); the honourable mind which is to
form a healthy judgement should have had no experience or contamination of evil
habits when young (all’ apeiron autȇn kai
akeraion dei kakȏn ȇthȏn nean ousan gegonenai, ei mellei kalȇ k’agathȇ ousa
krinein hugiȏs ta dikaia). And this is the reason (dio dȇ kai) why in youth good men often appear to be simple (euȇtheis neoi ontes hoi
epieikoi phainontati), and are easily practised by the dishonest
(kai euexapatȇtoi hupo
tȏn adikȏn)), because
they have no example of what evil is in their own souls (hate ouk echontes en heautois paradeigmata
homoiopathȇ tois ponȇrois).’
(408d10-409b2, tr. Jowett)
Having
insinuated himself into Plato’s mind as a man turned to philosophy, a man whose
memory was carried to the sight of the Forms – in terms of the Phaedran
Palinode – Polemarchus proved to be dishonest, as Plato saw it. He could not
forgive him. Polemarchus was a metic, a resident alien in Athens; in Republic VIII Plato points to ‘the metic
becoming equal with the citizen and the citizen with metic (metoikon de astȏi kai aston
metoikȏi exisousthai)’ as almost the last stage of deterioration
of democracy into tyranny (562e0-563a1, tr. Jowett), and in the Laws he stipulates that when a resident
alien acquires property that exceeds the property of the third class citizens,
he must take his property and leave the city within thirty days, and if he
overstays, he must be executed and his property confiscated (915b-c). Polemarchus
was executed by the Athenian aristocrats under the rule of the Thirty, and his
property was confiscated.
Socrates
closes his discussion with Polemarchus on justice with the words: ‘Do you know
(All oistha) whose saying I believe
it to be (hou moi dokei einai to rȇma), the
saying (to phanai) that justice is
benefiting friends (dikaion einai tous
men philous ȏphelein) and harming enemies (tous d’ echthrous blaptein)?’ –
Polemarchus: ‘Whose (Tinos;)?’ – Soc.
‘I believe it to be the saying of Periander (Oimai auto Periandrou) or Perdiccas (ȇ Perdikkou) or Xerxes (ȇ Xerxou) or
Ismenias the Theban (ȇ Ismȇniou tou Thȇbaiou) or of some other rich man who had a great
opinion of his own power (ȇ tinos allou mega
oiomenou dunasthai plousiou andros, 336a1-7).’
Adam notes ad loc.: ‘Periander, Xerxes and
Perdiccas are taken as types of tyrants … The expedition of Xerxes against
Greece is cited by Callicles in Gorgias
483 D in connection with the doctrine that might is right … Ismenias is
mentioned again in Meno 90 A as
having become rich … There can be no doubt that he is to be identified with the
Ismenias who in 395 took money from Timocrates the Rhodian, envoy of the
Persian King, in order to stir up war against Sparta.’
No comments:
Post a Comment