Plato says
in the Seventh Letter that Dionysius
had supposedly ‘written about what he heard from me’ (gegraphenai auton peri hȏn tote ȇkouen, 341b3-4). He therefore set out to
prove that what he told Dionysius cannot be expressed in writing. He concluded
his exposition as follows: ‘And this is the reason why (dio dȇ) every serious man (pas
anȇr spoudaios) in
dealing with really serious subjects (tȏn ontȏn
spoudaiȏn peri) carefully avoids writing (pollou dei mȇ grapsas pote), lest thereby he may possibly cast
them as a prey to the envy and stupidity of the public (en anthrȏpois eis phthonon kai
aporian katabalei).
In one word, then, our conclusion must be (heni
dȇ
ek toutȏn dei gignȏskein logȏi) that whenever one sees a man’s written compositions (hotan idȇi tis tou sungrammata
gegrammena) –
whether they be the laws of a legislator (eite
en nomois nomothetou) or anything else in any other form (eite en allois tisin att’ oun), – these
are not his most serious works (hȏs ouk ȇn toutȏi tauta spoudaiotata), if so be that the writer himself is serious (eiper est’ autos spoudaios): rather those works abide in the
fairest region he possesses (keitai de
pou en chȏrai tȇi kallistȇi tȏn toutou).
[Bury remarks: ‘i.e. in his head, the abode of unexpressed thoughts; cf. Tim.44d.’] If, however, these really are
his serious efforts (ei de ontȏs autȏi taut’ espoudasmena), and put into writing (en
grammasin etethȇ), it is not “the gods” but mortal men who “Then of a truth
themselves have utterly ruined his senses (“ex
ara dȇ
toi epeita” theoi men ou, brotoi de “phrenas ȏlesan autoi” [Bury refers to Homer, Il. vii. 360, xii. 234).’ (344c1-d2, tr.
Bury)
This passage
evokes the Phaedrus: ‘Any work, in
the past or in the future, whether by Lysias or anyone else (Hȏs eite Lusias ȇ tis allos pȏpote
egrapsen ȇ grapsei), whether composed in a private
capacity or in the role of a public man who by proposing a law becomes the
author of a political composition, is a matter of reproach to its author,
whether or no the reproach is actually voiced, if he regards it as containing
important truth of permanent validity (idiai
ȇ
dȇmosiai nomous titheis, sungramma politikon graphȏn kai
megalȇn tina en autȏi bebaiotȇta hȇgoumenos kai saphȇneian, houtȏ men oneidos
tȏi graphonti, eite tis phȇsin eite mȇ). For ignorance (to gar agnoein) of what is a waking
vision (hupar te) and what is a mere
dream-image (kai onar) of justice and
injustice (dikaiȏn kai adikȏn peri), good and evil (kai kakȏn kai agathȏn), cannot
truly be acquitted (ouk ekpheugei tȇi alȇtheiai) of
involving reproach (mȇ ouk eponeidiston einai), even if the mass of men extol it (oude an ho pas ochlos auto epainesȇi).’ (277d6-e3, tr. R. Hackforth)
Note the correspondence
between the Seventh Letter and the Phaedrus: Those, who think they
presented or can present in their writings the truth and not a mere dream-image
of the truth, by this very fact prove that they know nothing of justice and
injustice (dikaiȏn kai adikȏn peri), good and evil (kai kakȏn kai agathȏn), i.e. they
know nothing of the Forms. W. G. Tennemann referred to it in support of his
late dating of the Phaedrus in his System der platonischen Philosophie,
published in 1792 (vol. I, pp. iii-iv; 117-137; 203-207). But there is a
fundamental discrepancy between the Phaedrus
and the Seventh Letter. For in the Phaedrus Socrates contrasts the written
word, ‘which doesn’t know how to address
the right people, and not address the wrong’ (ouk epistatai legein hois dei ge
kai mȇ, 275e3), with the spoken word ‘which, together with knowledge (hos met’ epistȇmȇs), is written
in the soul of the learner (graphetai en
tȇi
tou manthanontos psuchȇi): that can defend itself (dunatos men amunai heautȏi), and knows to whom it should speak and to whom it should say nothing (epistȇmȏn de legein te kai sigan pros hous
dei).’-
Phaedrus: ‘You mean the living speech of the man who knows (Ton tou eidotos logon legeis zȏnta), the
speech that has soul (kai empsuchon),
of which the written discourse may fairly be called a kind of phantom (hou ho gegrammenos eidȏlon an ti
legoito dikaiȏs).’ – Socrates: ‘Precisely (Pantapasi men oun)’. (276a5-b1)
Socrates
concedes that a philosopher can take recourse to writing ‘for amusement’ (paidias charin, 276d2): ‘And when other
men resort to other pastimes (hotan de
alloi paidiais allais chrȏntai), regaling themselves with drinking (sumposiois te ardontes hautous) and such
like (heterois te hosa toutȏn adelpha), he
will doubtless prefer to indulge in the amusement I refer to (tot’ ekeinos, hȏs eoiken, anti toutȏn hois legȏ paizȏn diaxei).’ –
Phaedrus: ‘And what an excellent amusement you’re talking of, Socrates, in
contrast with a mean one (Pankalȇn legeis
para phaulȇn paidian, ȏ Sȏkrates) – that of a man who is able to
amuse himself with words (tou en logois
dunamenou paizein), when he discourses about justice and the other topics
you speak of (dikaiosunȇs kai allȏn
hȏn legeis muthologounta). – Socrates: ‘Yes indeed, dear Phaedrus (Esti gar, ȏ phile Phaidre, houtȏ). But far more excellent, I think,
is the serious treatment of them (polu d’
oimai kalliȏn spoudȇ peri auta gignetai), which employs the art of dialectic (hotan tis tȇi dialektikȇi technȇi
chrȏmenos). The dialectician
selects a soul of the right type (labȏn
psuchȇn prosȇkousan),
and in it he plants and sows his words founded on knowledge (phuteuȇi te kai speirȇi met’ epistȇmȇs logous),
words which can defend both themselves and him who planted them (hoi heautois tȏi te phuteusanti
boȇthein hikanoi), words which instead of remaining barren contain a seed (kai ouchi akarpoi alla echontes sperma) whence
new words grow up in new characters (hothen
alloi en allois ȇthesi phuomenoi); whereby the seed is vouchsafed
immortality (tout’ aei athanaton
parechein hikanoi), and its possessor the fullest measure of blessedness (kai ton echonta eudaimonein poiountes) that
man can attain unto (eis hoson anthrȏpȏi dunaton malista).’ – Phaedrus: ‘Yes, that is a far more excellent way (Polu gar tout’ eti kallion legeis).’
(276d5-277a5; Socrates’ and Phaedrus’ last entry is translated by Hackforth).
After the
debacle with Dionysius Plato in the Seventh
Letter was compelled to view the spoken word just as incapable of conveying
the truth about truth itself, as the written word. And he could not present
himself as a man ‘selecting a soul of the right type’ and in it sowing the
seeds of truth, a man ‘who knows to whom he should speak and to whom he should
say nothing’.
***
In the Seventh Letter Plato opened his
comprehensive refutation of Dionysius’ supposed claim with the words: ‘There is
an argument (esti gar tis logos) which holds good (alȇthȇs) against the man who ventures to put
anything whatever into writing on questions of this nature (enantios tȏi tolmȇsanti graphein tȏn toioutȏn kai hotioun);
it has often been stated by me (pollakis
men hup’ emou kai prosthen rȇtheis), and it seems suitable to the
present occasion (eoiken d’oun einai kai
nun lekteos, 342a3-6, tr. Harward).’ As the SL 344c1-d2 passage shows, first and foremost in Plato’s mind was
his disparagement of the written word in the Phaedrus. Pointedly so, for Phaedrus
was his first dialogue, and the fact that he held the same view about the
written word throughout his long and distinguished career as a writer gave his refutation
of Dionysius’ claim the desired weight.
Let me end
this post by noting a potent correspondence between the Phaedrus and the Laws. In
the Phaedrus Socrates maintains that
the philosopher and his beloved disciple, devoted to philosophy, are blessed
with happiness (makarion bion diagousin,
256a8-b1); the living words sowed in the soul with knowledge of truth give ‘their
possessor the fullest measure of blessedness (ton echonta eudaimonein poiountes) that man can attain unto (eis hoson anthrȏpȏi dunaton malista)’ (277a3-4).
In the Laws, the work of Plato’s ripe old age, the
Athenian Stranger – Plato felt like an Eleatic Stranger in Athens (in the Sophist and the Statesman) and an Athenian Stranger when imagining himself in Crete
(in the Laws) – asks what character
one must have if one is to live the best and most noble life (poios tis ȏn autos an kallista
diagagoi ton bion,
730b3-4). To this question he gives the following answer: ‘Truth (alȇtheia dȇ) heads the list of all things good,
for gods and men alike (pantȏn men
agathȏn theois hȇgeitai, pantȏn de anthrȏpois). Let anyone who intends to be happy
and blessed be its partner from the start (hȇs ho
genȇsesthai mellȏn makarios te kai eudaimȏn ex archȇs metochos eiȇ), so that he may live as much of his
life as possible a man of truth (hina hȏs pleiston
chronon alȇthȇs ȏn diabioi). You can trust a man like that (pistos gar).’ (730c1-4, tr. T. J.
Saunders)
Plato
identified the Forms with truth ever since he introduced them in the Phaedrus: ‘for assuredly we must be bold
to speak what is true (tolmȇteon gar
oun to ge alȇthes eipein), above all when our discourse is
upon truth
(allȏs
te kai peri alȇtheias legonta, 247b4-6, tr. Hackforth).’
No comments:
Post a Comment