Russell
writes in his History of Western
Philosophy, in the chapter on Socrates: ‘Socrates, in Plato’s works, always
pretends that he is only eliciting knowledge already possessed by the man he is
questioning; on this ground, he compares himself to a midwife. When, in the Phaedo and the Meno, he applies his method to geometrical problems, he has to ask
leading questions which any judge would disallow. The method is in harmony with
the doctrine of reminiscence, according to which we learn by remembering that
we knew in a former existence.’ (Russell, p. 97-98)
Russell
extrapolates from the Meno to the Phaedo. For in the Phaedo Socrates does not apply his method of questioning to
geometrical problems, although his having been doing so on previous occasions
is strongly affirmed in the dialogue.
In the
chapter on Plato’s Theory of Immortality Russell writes: ‘To return to the Phaedo: Cebes expresses doubts as to the
survival of the soul after death, and urges Socrates to offer arguments. This
he proceeds to do … The first argument is that all things which have opposites
are generated from their opposites … Now life and death are opposites, and
therefore each must generate the other. It follows that the souls of the dead
exist somewhere, and come back to earth in due course.’ (p. 137)
In the dialogue, at this point Cebes intervenes: “‘Yes, and
besides, Socrates,’ Cebes replied, ‘there’s also that theory (Kai mȇn, ephȇ ho Kebȇs hupolabȏn, kai kat’
ekeinon geton logon, ȏ Sȏkrates) you’re always putting forward (hon su eiȏthas thama legein), that our learning
is actually nothing but recollection (hoti
hȇmin hȇ mathȇsis ouk allo ti ȇ anamnȇsis tunchanei ousa); according to
that too (kai kata touton), if it’s
true (ei alȇthȇs estin), what we are
now reminded of we must have learned at some former time (anankȇ pou hȇmas en proterȏi tini chronȏi memathȇkenai ha nun
anamimnȇiskometha). But that would be impossible (touto de adunaton), unless our souls existed somewhere (ei mȇ ȇn pou hȇmin hȇ psuchȇ) before
being borne in this human form (prin en
tȏide tȏi anthrȏpinȏi eidei genesthai); so in this way too (hȏste kai tautȇi), it appears that the
soul is something immortal (athanaton hȇ
psuchȇ ti eoiken einai.’
‘Yes, what
are the proofs of those points, Cebes?’ put in Simmias (Alla, ȏ Kebȇs, ephȇ ho Simmias hupolabȏn, poiai toutȏn hai apodeixeis).
Remind me (hupomnȇson me), as I don’t
recall them very well at the moment (ou
gar sphodra en tȏi paronti memnȇmai).’
‘One
excellent argument,’ said Cebes (Heni men
logȏi, ephȇ ho Kebȇs, kallistȏi), ‘is that when people are questioned (hoti erȏtȏmenoi hoi anthrȏpoi), and if
questions are well put (ean tis kalȏs
erȏtai), they state the truth about everything for themselves (autoi legousin panta hȇi echei) – and
yet unless knowledge and a correct account were present within them (kaitoi ei mȇ etunchanen autois epistȇmȇ
enousa kai orthos logos), they’d be unable to do this (ouk an hoioi t’ ȇsan touto poiȇsai); thus, if one takes them to diagrams
(epeita ean tis epi ta diagrammata agȇi)
or anything else of that sort (ȇ allo ti
tȏn toioutȏn), one has there the plainest evidence that this is so (entautha saphestata katȇgorei hoti touto
houtȏs echei).’
‘But if that
doesn’t convince you, Simmias,’ said Socrates (Ei de mȇ tautȇi ge, ephȇ, peithȇi, ȏ Simmia, ho Sȏkratȇs), ‘then
see (skepsai) whether maybe you agree
if you look at it this way (an tȇide pȇi
soi skopoumenȏi sundoxȇi). Apparently you doubt (apisteis gar dȇ) whether what is called “learning” is recollection
(pȏs hȇ kaloumenȇ mathȇsis anamnȇsis
estin)?’
‘I don’t
doubt it’, said Simmias (Apistȏ men
egȏge, ȇ d’ hos ho Simmias, ou): ‘but I do need to undergo just what the
argument is about (auto de touto, ephȇ,
deomai pathein peri hou ho logos), to be “reminded” (anamnȇsthȇnai). Actually, from the way Cebes set about stating it,
I do almost recall it (kai schedon ge ex
hȏn Kebȇs epecheirȇse legein ȇdȇ memnȇmai) and am nearly convinced (kai peithomai); but I’d like, none the
less (ouden ment’an hȇtton), to hear
(akouoimi) now how you set about
stating it yourself (nun pȇi su epecheirȇsas
legein).’
‘I’ll put it
this way (Tȇid’ egȏge, ȇ d’ hos). We
agree (homologoumen gar), I take it (dȇpou), that if anyone is to be reminded
of a thing (ei tis ti anamnȇsthȇsetai)
he must have known that thing at some time previously (dein auton touto proteron pote epistasthai)?’” (Phaedo 72e3-73c2, tr. David Gallop)
The way, in
which Socrates is about to prove that ‘what is called “learning” is
recollection’ has nothing to do with geometrical problems, it is concerned with
the Forms. Socrates proves the point concerning the notion of equality, and
then he says: ‘Our present argument concerns the beautiful itself, and the good
itself, and just and holy, no less than the equal (ou gar peri tou isou nun ho logos hȇmin mallon ti ȇ peri autou tou
kalou kai autou tou agathou, kai dikaiou kai hosiou); in fact, as I say (kai, hoper legȏ), it concerns everything
on which we set this seal (peri hapantȏn
hois episphragizometha), “what it is” (to
“auto ho esti”), in the questions we ask (kai en tais erȏtȇsesin erȏtȏntes) and in the answers we give (kai en tais apokrisesin apokrinomenoi,
75c10-d3, tr. Gallop).’
***
It is worth
noting that the ‘proof’ or the Theory of Recollection by questioning a person
concerning geometrical problems, ‘if one takes them to diagrams or anything
else of that sort’, is accepted neither by Cebes, nor by Simmias, as valid.
Cebes qualifies it with the words ‘if it’s true’ (ei alȇthȇs estin, 72e4). Simmias is only ‘nearly convinced (kai schedon ge peithomai, 73b8-9), and
Socrates expects him to be unconvinced – ‘but if that does not convince you’ (ei de mȇ tautȇi ge peithȇi, 73b3), while
his own belief in its validity appears to be unshaken.
In the
opening paragraph I am quoting Russell’s ‘When, in the Phaedo and the Meno, he
[i.e. Socrates] applies his method to geometrical problems, he has to ask
leading questions which any judge would disallow.’ On any dating of these two
dialogues I have come across, Plato’s publication of the Meno precedes that of the Phaedo.
On the generally accepted dating both were written after Plato’s first journey
to Italy and Sicily, where Plato got in contact with the Pythagoreans: the Meno with its Theory of Recollection is
the first result of that acquaintance, the theory of Forms developed in the Phaedo comes next. On that dating, one
might speculate that when Plato wrote the Phaedo
he became aware that in the Meno his
Socrates ‘has to ask leading questions which any judge would disallow’, and that
this is why he presented Cebes and Simmias as unconvinced by it.
In The Lost Plato in Chapter 10 entitled
‘Plato versus Anytus’ I argue that Plato must have written the Meno prior to the indictment and death
of Socrates: ‘In 401, two years before Socrates died, Meno took part in the
ill-fated attempt of Cyrus the younger to dethrone the Persian king Artaxerxes.
He joined Cyrus’ army at the head of a mercenary contingent from Thessaly
(Xenophon, Anabasis I.ii.6) and after
Cyrus fell he became instrumental in the capture of the Greek commanders by the
Persians (Xen. An. II.iii-vi). In the
Meno, Socrates in his closing words
exhorts Meno to persuade Anytus, Meno’s host, of all that he himself has been
persuaded by Socrates in their discussioin (su
de ta auta tauta haper autos pepeisai peithe kai ton xenon tonde Anuton),
so that he might become more gentle (hina
praioteros ȇi): ‘if you succeed in persuading him, you will benefit the
Athenians’ (hȏs ean peisȇis touton, estin
hoti kai Athȇnaious onȇseis, 100b7-c2). If Plato wrote the Meno after the death of Socrates, as is
currently believed, both he himself and his readers were bound to think of
Anytus first and foremost as the principal accuser of Socrates, and of Meno as
the scoundrel (hȏs ponȇros, Xenophon,
Anabasis II.vi.29) who betrayed the
Greek army commanders to the Persians. I cannot see how Plato could have
written the Meno in these circumstances. This is why I date the dialogue prior
to Meno’s involvement in Cyrus’ military expedition.’
On my dating
of the Meno, this dialogue with its
‘leading questions which any judge would disallow’ couldn’t but stand in the
way of Cebes’ and Simmias’ accepting Socrates’ prowess in discussing
geometrical problems as a convincing proof of the Theory of Recollection.
No comments:
Post a Comment