The
international symposium ‘The Significance of the Republic and the Laws
in Plato’s Thought’ was held in Prague on April 4-5th, 1997, on the
occasion of the founding of the ‘Czech Plato Society’. On that occasion I gave
a paper on ‘Joining the Beginning to the End’, which was then published in the
‘Proceedings of the First Symposium Platonicum Pragense’. I republished it on
my website with permission of the publishing house OIKOYMENH. I bring here an extract from it, which is
directly relevant to Rowe’s argument ‘4. Other clear connections with Laws
10, as has long been noticed, are to be found in the arguments for immortality
(245c-246a)’. I lived still in Oxford, and so I had access to relevant
secondary literature.
Let me start
with the beginning and the end of the paper:
‘A Stranger
from Athens, Cleinias from Crete, and Megillus from Sparta walk along the road
from Cretan City of Cnossus to the cave and temple of Zeus. The Athenian asks
about the divine provenance of the laws in Crete and in Sparta, and his fellow
travellers are happy to answer his queries. The journey promises to be
agreeable, for along the road there will be convenient shady places under the
lofty trees where they can relax; this is important, for they are old, all
three of them, and the heat of the day is upon them (pnigous ontos ta nun,
625b3).
This is the
opening scene of the Laws. It reminds the reader of the Phaedrus;
there too the discussion takes place in the countryside, Socrates feels himself
a stranger (230c), he and Phaedrus enjoy the shade of a lofty tree (230b), and
the heat of the day is upon them (en tȏi pnigei, 258e7). Thesleff noticed the
similarity and inferred from it that Plato began to write the Laws
shortly after the Phaedrus. (H.Thesleff, Studies in Platonic
Chronology, Societas Scientiarum Fennica, Helsinki, 1982, p. 187) The
ancient tradition according to which the Phaedrus was Plato’s first
dialogue invites a different explanation: when Plato in his old age embarked on
writing the Laws he returned in his thought to his first work.’
***
‘The Phaedrus
ends with Phaedrus’ wish to partake of Socrates’ philosophy: “For friends share
all things in common” (koina gar ta tȏn philȏn,
279c2-3). When the Athenian Stranger decides to join the foundation of the
proposed city, he declares it to be “a common task for friends” (ȏ philoi, en koinȏi kai mesȏi eoiken hȇmin keisthai, 968e7-8).’
***
***
‘The
similarities concerning the notion of the soul in the Phaedrus and in
the Laws have led a number of scholars to believe that the two share the
same proof of the immortality of the soul, from which they derived a strong
argument for the late dating of the former dialogue. But this is wrong, for
although the soul is defined in both as the principle of motion, there is a
fundamental difference between the two. In the Phaedrus the soul is
proved to be immortal because it is declared to be the ungenerated first
principle (archȇ de agenȇton,
245d1); in the Laws it is emphasized that the soul is the generated
principle of motion (archȇn ara kinȇseȏs … genomenȇn,
895b4, cf. 892a-c). What is proved in the Laws is not the immortality of
the soul, but only its priority to all bodily matter, to which the soul imparts
motion (dedeiktai psuchȇ tȏn pantȏn presbutatȇ, genomenȇ ge archȇ kinȇseȏs,
896b2-3). In other words, Plato is arguing that the soul was generated before
the body (psuchȇn proteran gegonenai sȏmatos, 896c1-2). What stands between the Phaedrus and the Laws
is the creation of the soul by the demiurge, which Plato described in the Timaeus.
In order to introduce the Phaedran notion of soul in the Laws, Plato had
to revise it.’
In the note
accompanying the opening sentence of this paragraph I wrote: ‘See e.g. H.
Thesleff, Studies in Platonic Chronology, op. cit. p. 177 (n. 56): “…
the proof of immortality in Phdr. 245c-246a is much more sophisticated
than R X 617dff., and is adopted again in Leg.X 894b ff, cf. de Vries 1969. 9.” G.J.
de Vries, A Commentary on the Phaedrus of Plato, Amsterdam 1969,
p. 9: “A stronger argument [for the post-Republic dating of the Phaedrus]
may be found in the proof of the soul’s immortality, offered in the Phaedrus;
it is hardly conceivable that Plato would have published the rather clumsy
argumentation of Rep. X if the better argument of Phdr. (used
in Laws too), based on the soul’s motion, had been at his disposal.”
See further L. Robin, La Théorie Platonicienne de l’amour, Paris 1908 (repr. 1964), pp. 70 and
97.'
No comments:
Post a Comment