In the
chapter on ‘The Theory of Ideas’ in his History
of Western Philosophy Russel views Plato’s Forms through the looking glass
of the last book of the Republic as
God’s creations, and he is wrong in doing so. He is particularly wrong when he
maintains that ‘according to the metaphysical part of the doctrine, the word
“cat” means a certain ideal cat, “the
cat”, created by God, and unique (p. 123)’, for Plato in the tenth book of the Republic speaks of God as the maker of
the Form of bed (597b), and he introduces the whole discussion by contemplating
the Forms of table and of bed – ‘of these two men-made implements’ (ideai ge pou peri tauta ta skeuȇ duo,
596b3) – but he does not speak of God as creator of any animal or any natural
object. This clearly indicated to Plato’s followers that the Forms of which he
speaks as created by God were not the real Forms, for on Aristotle’s testimony
Plato maintained that there are as many Forms as there are natural objects (hoposa physei, Met. 1070a18).
Russell’s
mistake raises a serious question: Why did Plato in the last book of the Republic introduce the notion of God as
creator of Forms – for that’s what he appears to be doing.
Adam in his
Commentary on the Republic appears to
have grappled with this problem. At 597b5-6 Socrates says: ‘Here we find three
beds: one existing in nature, which is made by God’. On the margin of my Oxford
edition of the text I wrote Adam’s note: ‘If God and the Idea of Good are the
same, Plato is merely saying in theological language what he formerly said in
philosophical, when he derived the ousia
of all other Ideas from the Idea of Good (VI 509 B).’
Pace Adam, I don’t think that the God
creating the Form of bed in Republic
X can be identified with the Idea of Good in Republic VI 509 B: ‘The Good
not only infuses the power of being known into all things known (Kai tois gignȏskomenois toinun mȇ monon to
gignȏskesthai phanai hupo tou agathou pareinai), but also bestows upon them
their being and existence (alla kai to
einai te kai tȇn ousian hup’ ekeinou autois proseinai), and yet the Good is
not existence (ouk ousias ontos tou
agathou), but lies far beyond it in dignity and power (all’ eti epekeina tȇs ousias presbeiai kai dunamei huperechontos).’
(509b6-10, tr. B. Jowett)
I believe
that Plato’s assertion that being and existence is bestowed upon the Forms (autois proseinai) from the Good (hup’ ekeinou) should not be viewed in
terms of the creation of the Forms by God discussed in Republic X, but rather in terms of the community or association of
Forms (koinȏnias allȇlȏn, 254c5),
which Plato discusses in the Sophist
(see 254a-d) and which he seems to be indicating in Republic V, where he says that each Form is one, but because of the
association of the Forms (allȇlȏn
koinȏniai) each appears to be many (polla
phainesthai hekaston, 476a5-7).
What is here
decisive is the way Socrates speaks of God as the creator of the Form of bed in
Republic X, where he says that God
‘made one bed in nature and one only (mȇ
pleon ȇ mian en tȇi phusei apergasasthai auton klinȇn)’ for ‘even if He had
made but two (hoti ei duo monas poiȇseien),
a third would still appear behind them (palin
an mia anaphaneiȇ) of which they again both possessed the form (hȇs ekeinai an au amphoterai to eidos
echoien), and that would be the real bed and not the two others (kai eiȇ an ho estin klinȇ ekeinȇ all’ ouch
hai duo) (597c2-9, tr. Jowett). This cannot be brought into harmony with
the Good that bestows being on the Forms in Republic
VI.
The question
remains: Why did Plato in the last book of the Republic introduce the notion of God as creator of Forms?
I have
argued in my first entry on Russell’s chapter on ‘The Theory of Ideas’ (posted
on July 23) that in his discussion of Forms in Republic VII Plato’s eyes were repeatedly drawn to the days of
Socrates and in particular to Socrates’ death in the hands of the Athenian
jury. In view of this it would appear that Plato was afraid that his detractors
might view the Forms as ‘introduction of new deities’ – the charge for which
Socrates was sentenced to death – and that he conceived the last book of the Republic so as to throw dust in their
eyes. But how could one even contemplate this explanation, when in the Phaedrus Plato’s Socrates proclaims that
‘God has his divinity by virtue of being with the Forms’ (pros hoisper theos ȏn theios estin, 249c6)’ – if the post-Republic dating of the Phaedrus is to be adhered to?
The
situation dramatically changes if we view the Phaedrus in accordance with the ancient biographic tradition as
Plato’s first dialogue written during Socrates’ life, dialogue written prior to
the death of Polemarchus in the hands of the Thirty tyrants, as I have argued
in The Lost Plato on my website. For
on this dating Plato as the author of the Phaedrus
was protected by the amnesty announced by the victorious democrats after their
defeat of the Thirty. Any intelligent reader could see that the Forms discussed
in Republic V-VII are the Forms
introduced in the Phaedrus. Plato
therefore had to devise a new protection; this he did by presenting god as the
creator of forms in the last book of the Republic.
No comments:
Post a Comment