In ‘Plato’s defence of Forms in the Parmenides’ (on my website) I’ve argued that Plato wrote the Parmenides after his return from
Syracuse in 366 B.C., and that he wrote it for his disciples in the Academy to fortify
them against any possible attacks against the theory of the Forms after his
planned return to Syracuse. He did so by exposing the theory of Forms of a very
young Socrates, with which the latter challenged Parmenides’ ‘All is one’
thesis, to Parmenides’ criticism. The discussion was diligently rehearsed by
Plato’s half-brother Antiphon; in the dialogue Plato’s brother Adeimantus (and
implicitly his brother Glaucon, who accompanies Adeimantus) vouches for it.
This means that Plato himself, like his brothers was well aware of all those
arguments against the Forms; these arguments had no relevance to Forms that he
himself discovered. And so he can let his Parmenides step out of his historical
persona, predict the coming of an exceptional man who will discover Forms
immune against all ‘refutations’ (Parm.
133b4-135b2).
Plato returned to Athens in 366 B.C. with the intention to
return to Syracuse in a year. When his stay in Athens became protracted, Plato
had to think of finding ways how to fortify Dionysius against the attacks
against his theory of Forms by sophists with which Dionysius surrounded
himself. The Parmenides became suddenly
primarily important in Plato’s relation to Dionysius. But there was a problem.
The Parmenides as it was originally
written for Plato’s disciples in the Academy pointed to the Republic as its necessary companion.
This connection became problematic, for the main tenet animating the Republic, the postulated unity between
philosophy and political power, became the main target of Plato’s detractors in
Syracuse, and thus of Dionysius’ suspicions: ‘What does Plato really want?’
Moreover, Plato needed to present Dionysius with a dialogue that nothing the
sophists around him could offer him might match. And so he wrote the Symposium in which he conjures up an
ideal philosopher in the guise of a priestess Diotima, whom nobody can accuse
of hankering after political power. As Plato’s stay in Athens became even more
protracted, this point had to be made more strongly and more explicitly. And so
Plato wrote the Sophist in which the
Eleatic Stranger maintains that Sophist, Statesman, and Philosopher are
different from each other.
In the Parmenides
itself Plato did his best to show that Parmenides’ arguments against the Forms
only looked like saying something important, but in fact were a pack of
falsities; he emphasized this by the fact that Parmenides’ arguments against
the Forms diligently memorised by Antiphon did not turn the latter to
philosophy; Adeimantus in the preamble to the dialogue mentions that when
Antiphon grew up he devoted himself to horsemanship (Parm. 126c). This point is emphasised in the Symposium; in its preamble we meet with Glaucon who was interested
in doing anything else but philosophy. Obviously, Parmenides’ arguments against
the Forms he heard Antiphon memorizing turned him away from philosophy; it was
Socrates’ speech on love presented at Agathon’s banquet, which Apollodorus
narrated to him, that made him a worthy partner in discussion with Socrates in
the Republic.
As Plato secured the connection between the Parmenides and the Republic in the preamble to the Parmenides,
and the connection between the Symposium,
Parmenides, and the Republic in the preamble to the Symposium, so he secured the
all-important connection of the Sophist
to the Parmenides in the preamble to
the Sophist. Theodorus opens the
dialogue by introducing the Eleatic Stranger to Socrates as ‘a disciple of
Parmenides and Zeno’ (hetairon tȏn amphi
Parmenidȇn te kai Zȇnȏna, 216a3-4), and Socrates asks the Stranger whether
he prefers to define the Sophist, Statesman, and Philosopher my making a long
oration, or by the method of questions (di’
erȏtȇseȏn), ‘which Parmenides employed when he was going through very
beautiful arguments (diexionti logous
pankalous) in a discussion at which I was present as a young man; he was at
that time already very old’ (217c).
The whole point of the Parmenides
is to show that arguments Parmenides had raised against the Forms were
falsities (Parm. 133b7) and only
appeared to be ‘saying something’ (dokein
ti legein, 135a6), while in fact they were empty talk. It appears that in
the Sophist Plato strongly
re-emphasizes this point. For in the Parmenides,
Parmenides ends his criticism of the theory of Forms of the young Socrates by
pointing to him that he began to define the Forms too early: ‘Train yourself
more thoroughly while you are still young; drag yourself more through what is
generally regarded as useless, and condemned by the multitude as idle talk (adoleschia).’ (Parm. 135d, tr. R. E. Allen) Adoleschia
‘idle talk’ comes to the fore in the Sophist
within the framework of the Stranger’s definition of the Sophist as an Eristic
that differs from the adoleschikos,
the man of ‘idle talk’, only in so far as he earns his money by getting engaged
in disputations, whereas the adoleschikos
neglects his own affairs and gets impoverished because of his delight in
disputations (Soph. 225c-d). In the Sophist the Eristic is characterised as antilogikos (225b10), a man pitting
argument against argument. When Socrates asks Parmenides what does this
training, viewed as adoleschia,
consist of, the latter explains: ‘It is necessary to examine the consequences
that follow from the hypothesis, not only if each thing is hypothesized to be,
but also if that same thing is hypothesized not to be.’ (135e9-136a2, tr.
Allen).
No comments:
Post a Comment