I have suggested
that Plato wrote the Parmenides after
his return from Sicily in 366 to function as his
substitute jointly with the Republic
after his planned definitive departure from Athens, i. e. before leaving Athens
for Sicily in 360. Jointly, these two dialogues were to protect his disciples
against the hostile questioning of the theory of Forms. But as Plato informs us
in the Seventh Letter, he left Sicily
in 366 having agreed to return there when Dionysius would invite him back,
after making the affairs in Sicily safe for him, ending the war in which he was
engaged. This means that his main preoccupation must have been with his
forthcoming departure for Sicily, and thus with Dionysius; the Second Letter, written in this period,
corroborates this supposition.
Plato opens the Second
Letter by voicing Dionysius’ disquiet: ‘I hear from Archedemus that you
think that not only I myself should keep quiet but my friends also from doing
or saying anything bad about you’. After insisting that Dionysius’ worries are
groundless, caused by false insinuations of sophists, Plato answers Dionysius’
question how ‘after this (meta tauta)
you and I ought to behave to each other’: ‘If you altogether despise
philosophy, leave it alone. If, again, you have been taught by someone else or
have yourself invented better doctrines than mine, hold them in honour. But if
you are contented with my doctrines (ei
ara ta par hêmȏn soi areskei), then you should hold me also in special
honour … if you honour me, you will be thought to be honouring philosophy (philosophian doxeis timan); and the very
fact that you have studied other systems as well (hoti dieskopeis kai allous) will gain you the credit, in the eyes
of many, of being a philosopher yourself.’ (312b2-c4, tr. Bury).
In the Parmenides
Plato leaves ‘unanswered’ the objections against the Forms raised by
Parmenides, noting that those objections, and many others on top of those,
pertain to the Forms of necessity’ (anankaion
echein ta eidê, 135a1), so that ‘only a man of considerable natural gifts’ will be able to
understand that there are the Forms (135a5-b2). As the introductory scene to
the dialogue clearly indicates, Plato himself was acquainted with such
objections since his early days; the message, which is thus incorporated in the
Parmenides, is that no objections
against the Forms can sway a man who can properly contemplate them. This
message was relevant both concerning Dionysius and Plato’s disciples in the
Academy. The Parmenides points to the
Republic, where the road to the Forms
is delineated; the philosophical problem concerning ‘the King of All’, which
Dionysius wants Plato to clarify to him, and which Plato in the Second Letter explains ‘in riddles’,
points to the Good, in which Plato’s theory of the Forms culminates in the Republic, yet the Republic was far from ideal as a point of reference as far as
Dionysius was concerned, for it was inseparably linked to the main thought that
brought Plato to Sicily in the first place, the thought that philosophers
should obtain royal power or kings become philosophers, and thus with
Dionysius’ fears concerning Dion’s and possibly even Plato’s political
aspirations. (Dion was brother-in-law and son-in-law of Dionysius’ father, Dionysius
I. When Dionysius died in 367, Dion believed that the young Dionysius might
become the philosopher-king under the guidance of Plato.)
***
Plutarch says in the Life of Dion: ‘Dion had hopes, as it seems likely, that by means of
the visit of Plato he could mitigate the arrogance and excessive severity of
the tyranny, and convert Dionysius into a fit and lawful ruler; but if
Dionysius should oppose his efforts and refuse to be softened, he had
determined to depose him and restore the civil power to the Syracusan people;
not that he approved of a democracy, but he thought it altogether better than a
tyranny in lack of a sound and healthy aristocracy. Such was the condition of
affairs when Plato came to Sicily, and in the first instances he met with
astonishing friendliness and honour. For a royal chariot, magnificently
adorned, awaited him as he left his trireme, and the tyrant offered a sacrifice
of thanksgiving for the great blessing that had been bestowed upon his
government. Moreover, the modesty that characterized his banquets, the decorum
of the courtiers, and the mildness of the tyrant himself in all his dealings
with the public, inspired the citizens with marvellous hopes of his
reformation. There was also something like a general rush for letters and
philosophy, and the palace was filled with dust, as they say, owing to the
multitude of geometricians there (the translator Bernadotte Perrin notes:
‘Geometrical figures were traced in loose sand strewn upon the floor.’). After
a few days had passed, there was one of the customary sacrifices of the country
in the palace grounds; and when the herald, as was the custom, prayed that the
tyranny might abide unshaken for many generations, it is said that Dionysius,
who was standing near, cried: “Stop cursing us!” This quite vexed Philistius
and his party, who thought that time and familiarity would render Plato’s
influence almost irresistible, if now, after a brief intimacy, he had so
altered and transformed the sentiments of the youthful prince. They therefore
no longer abused Dion one by one and secretly, but all together and openly,
saying that he was manifestly enchanting and bewitching Dionysius with Plato’s
doctrines, in order that the tyrant might of his own accord relinquish and give
up the power, which Dion would then assume … As a consequence of all this,
Dionysius became at first suspicious, and afterwards more openly angry and
hostile …’ (Plutarch, Dion xii. 2 -
xiv. 4, tr. Bernadotte Perrin) – As we can learn from Plutarch’s Life of Dion xxxvi, he drew on the best
available historical sources: Ephorus of Cume (c. 405-330 B.C.) and Timaeus of
Tauromenium (c.356-260 B.C.).
Plutarch’s account resonates with Plato’s account
in the Seventh Letter: ‘On my arrival
I found Dionysius’s kingdom all full of civil strife and of slanderous stories
brought to the court concerning Dion. So I defended him, so far as I was able,
though it was little I could do; but about three months later, charging Dion
with plotting against the tyranny, Dionysius set him aboard a small vessel and
drove him out with ignominy. After that all of us who were Dion’s friends were
in alarm lest he should punish any of us on a charge of being accomplices in
Dion’s plot; and regarding me a report actually went abroad in Syracuse that I
had been put to death by Dionysius as being responsible for all the events of
that time. But when Dionysius perceived us all in this state of mind, he was
alarmed lest our fears should bring about some worse result; so he was for
receiving us all back in a friendly manner; and, moreover, he kept consoling me
and bidding me be of good courage and begging me by all means to remain
(329b7-d5) … He became indeed more and more devoted as time advanced, according
as he grew familiar with my disposition and character, but he was desirous that
I should praise him more than Dion and regard him rather than Dion as my
special friend, and this triumph he was marvellously akin to achieve (kai thaumastȏs ephilonikei pros to toiouton).
But the best way to achieve this, if it was to be achieved – namely, by
occupying himself in learning and in listening to discourses on philosophy and
by associating with me – this he always shirked owing to his dread of the talk
of slanderers, lest he might be hampered in some measure and Dion might
accomplish his designs. I, however, put up with all this, holding fast the
original purpose with which I had come, in the hope that he might possibly gain
a desire for the philosophic life; but he, with his resistance, won the day
(330a2-b7, tr. Bury).’
***
I have pointed out that Plato wrote the Parmenides to help his disciples in disregarding
and discarding any arguments against the Forms as irrelevant, and that it could
do so only hand in hand with the Republic
in which the Forms are demonstrated as the only objects that can be truly known
– all other objects are subjects of mere opinion. In so far as it was designed
to function as a substitute for Plato in his absence, the Parmenides was as relevant for Dionysius after Plato’s departure
from Sicily in 366 and before his planned return, as it was to be relevant for Plato’s
disciples in the Academy after Plato’s planned departure from Athens. But since
the Parmenides could not fulfil this
function on its own, and since the reference to the Republic was unhelpful, to say the least, Plato had to write a new
text with Dionysius in mind, which would fulfil the same role concerning him
that the Republic was to play
concerning the Academy. Plato’s brothers Adeimantus and Glaucon figure
prominently in the introductory scene in the Parmenides, pointing the reader to the Republic, in which they play a leading role side by side with
Socrates. Glaucon links the Parmenides
to the Symposium. I shall argue that
in the light of the Second Letter, Plato wrote the Symposium after the Parmenides, so
that these two dialogues should defend his philosophic position during his
absence from Sicily. Glaucon was the obvious choice for the task of linking
these two dialogues and supplanting the Republic
as far as Dionysius was concerned. In the Republic
Socrates characterizes Glaucon as a man devoted to Eros (anêr erȏtikos, 474d4) just after telling him that ‘until philosophers are kings in
their cities, or the kings and princes of this world have the spirit and power
of philosophy, and political greatness (dunamis
politikê) and wisdom (philosophia) meet in one, and those commoner natures who pursue
either to the exclusion of the other are compelled to stand aside, cities will
never have rest of their evils’ (Rep.
473c11-d5, tr. B. Jowett); in the Symposium Glaucon is eager to hear all
the speeches devoted to Eros (peri tȏn
erȏtikȏn logȏn, 172b2), which were spoken at Agathon’s banquet. As Plutarch
pointed out, after Plato’s arrival to Sicily Dionysius did not abandon his
predilection for banquets, but these were now characterized by modesty (aidȏs sumposiȏn, xiii, 3); the Symposium was an obvious theme for a
text that in Plato’s absence Dionysius was to compare with anything that the
sophists at his court could present him with.
Envisaging his return to Sicily, Plato had to
compose a writing that would successfully compete not only with any writings of
the sophists, but with anything they could offer Dionysius in their lectures
and discussions on philosophy. In the Symposium
Plato does his best to fulfil this task: ‘the Symposium is perhaps the most brilliant of all Plato’s achievements
as a dramatic artist’. (A. E. Taylor, Plato,
1926, p. 209) But Plato had to make it clear to Dionysius that if he really
wanted to devote himself to philosophy, no writing of his, however brilliant it
might be, could be a substitute for his presence and the power of his spoken
word. This is why he says in the Second
Letter, referring to ‘the King of All’, i.e. the Good that reigns as King in the intellectual sphere in the Republic (basileuein tou noêtou genous te kai topou, Rep. 509d2): ‘I myself have never yet
written anything on these subjects, and no treatise of Plato exists or will
exist, but those which now bear his name belong to a Socrates become fair and
young ‘(314c2-4, tr. Bury). This pronouncement performs both these tasks; it
ostensibly refers to all Plato’s writings, but in particular to the Parmenides, in which Plato presents us
with a young Socrates, and even more so to the Symposium, in which Apollodorus ‘met Socrates fresh from the bath
and sandalled’. And as the sight of Socrates wearing sandals was unusual, Apollodorus
‘asked him whither he was going that he had been converted into such a beau: -
“To a banquet at Agathon’s”, he replied … “I have put on my finery, because he
is such a fine man” (hina kalos para
kalon iȏ).’ (174a3-9, tr. Jowett). Socrates in the Symposium made himself unusually beautiful, and in his contribution
to the banquet he takes us to his youth; Socrates presented in the speech was
presumably even younger than he is in the Parmenides.
In the Second
Letter Plato sets aside the view of the Republic that the philosophers can accomplish the greatest things (ta megista) as philosophers only when
they acquire royal power (Rep. 497a); it is only an advisory role to Dionysius, as a
teacher and companion, that he now appears to aspire to: ‘It is natural for
wisdom and great power to come together, and they are for ever pursuing and
seeking each other and consorting together’ (310e5-6, tr. Bury).
Referring to his doctrine concerning the Good, the
King of All, Plato tells Dionysius: ‘There are hardly any doctrines, I believe,
which sound more absurd than these to the vulgar, or, on the other hand, more
admirable and inspired (thaumastotera kai
enthousiastikȏtera) to men of fine disposition (pros tous euphueis)’ (314a2-5, tr. Bury). The Symposium presents the
ascent to the Form of Beauty as the most admirable and inspired journey, which
only a man of fine disposition can aspire to.
Plato in the Second
Letter appealed to Dionysius’ philotimia,
his love of glory: ‘Now as for you and me, the relation in which we stand to
each other is really this. There is not a single Greek, one may say, to whom we
are unknown, and our intercourse is a matter of common talk; and you may be
sure of this, that it will be common talk also in days to come, because so many
have heard tell of it owing to its duration and its publicity (310d6-e4) … Now
my object in saying all this is to make it clear, that when we ourselves die
men’s talk about us will not likewise be silenced; so that we must be careful
about it. We must necessarily, it seems, have a care also for the future,
seeing that, by some law of nature, the most slavish men pay no regard to it,
whereas the most upright do all they can to ensure that they shall be well
spoken in the future’ (311c1-7, tr. Bury).
In the Seventh
Letter Plato characterizes Dionysius as follows: ‘Now besides being
naturally gifted otherwise (ho de oute
allȏs estin aphuês) with a capacity for learning (pros tên tou manthanein dunamin) Dionysius has an extraordinary
love of glory (philotimos te thaumastȏs)’
(338d6-7, tr. Bury).’ In the Symposium
Plato points to the love of glory as a step in the ascent to the Form of Beauty.
Diotima tells Socrates: ‘I am persuaded that all men do all things, and the
better they are the more they do them (hosȏi
an ameinous ȏsi, tosoutȏi mallon) in the hope of the glorious fame of
immortal virtue (huper arêtes athanatou
kai toiautês doxês eukleous); for they desire the immortal’ (208d7-e1, tr.
Jowett).
Bury translates the lines 338d6-7 in the Seventh Letter as if Plato put his
finger on three distinct character traits of Dionysius: ‘being naturally gifted
otherwise’, ‘with a capacity for learning’, and ‘having an extraordinary love
of glory’. But Plato speaks of only two character traits, for he links
Dionysius’ extraordinary love of glory with his capacity for learning; it was
his capacity for learning of which he was extraordinarily proud and which
attracted him to Plato even after the expulsion of Dion. It is to this trait
that Plato appeals in the Symposium,
where Diotima extols wisdom (phronêsin),
and in particular ‘the greatest and fairest sort of wisdom by far, which is
concerned with the ordering of states and families, and which is called temperance
and justice’ (209a5-8, tr. Jowett).
In the Symposium
Plato chose a priestess Diotima as the accomplished guide to the Form of Beauty;
she can extol the virtue of a statesman without arousing any suspicion that she
herself aspired to political supremacy by bringing philosophy and true politics
into personal unity. In the Epistle VIII
– ‘written some months after the seventh letter, i.e. shortly before Callippus,
the murderer of Dion, had been driven out in turn by Hipparinus, the son of
Dionysius the Elder and the nephew of Dion’ – Plato advises the three
antagonistic parties to unite and choose three kings, who were to be the chief
priests. (See Bury’s ’Prefatory note’ to Epistle VIII)
In the Symposium
Aristophanes in his speech refers to the dispersal of the Arcadians into
villages by the Lacedaemonians, which took place in 385 B.C., fourteen years
after the death of Socrates (193a); Diotima in her speech to the young Socrates
refers to Aristophanes’ speech as ‘a myth’ (legetai
de tis logos, 205d10); when Socrates ended Diotima’s narrative,
Aristophanes ‘was beginning to say something in answer to the allusion which
Socrates has made to his own speech’ (212c4-6). With Dionysius in mind, Plato
thus emphasizes that Diotima’s speech was his speech, composed for Dionysius’
benefit.
By far the most important connection between the Second Letter and the Symposium is the dramatization in the
latter of ‘the question, which is the cause of all the mischief’ (to erȏtêma ho pantȏn aition esti kakȏn,
313a4), formulated in the former. In the Second
Letter Plato says: ‘The human soul strives to learn, looking to the things
that are akin to itself, whereof none is fully perfect. But as to the King and
the objects I have mentioned (hapanta ta
kala, ‘all the beautiful things’ in 312e3), they are of quite different
quality. In the next place the soul inquires – “Well then, what quality have
they?” But the cause of all the mischief, O son of Dionysius and Doris, lies in
this very question, or rather in the travail which this question creates in the
soul; and unless a man delivers himself from this he will never really attain
the truth.’ (312e4-313a6, tr. Bury)
Bury’s “Well then, what quality have they?” stands
for Plato’s alla poion ti mên; when we consider this question and Agathon’s
opening to his speech in the original, it becomes apparent that Agathon’s
speech in the Symposium can be seen
as a dramatization of this question in the Second
Letter. In Jowett’s translation, Agathon opens his speech as follows: ‘The
previous speakers, instead of praising the god of Love, and unfolding his
nature, appear to have congratulated mankind on the benefits which he confers
upon them. But I would rather praise the god first, and then speak of his
gifts; this is always the right way of praising everything.’ (194e5-195a3) Jowett’s
‘But I would rather praise the god first, and then speak of his gifts; this is
always the right way of praising everything’ stands for hopoios de tis autos ȏn (but of what quality is he) tauta edȏrêsato (who gave these gifts), oudeis eirêken (nobody has said). Heis de tropos orthos pantos epainou peri
pantos (but there is one right way of praising everything), logȏi dielthein (to discourse in
detail) hoios hoiȏn aitios ȏn tunchanei peri hou an ho logos êi (of what quality happens to be he of
whom one speaks and of what quality
are the things of which he is the cause, 194e7-195a3). To make the connection
apparent, I used Bury’s ‘of what quality’ to render Agathon’s hopoios,
hoios, and hoiȏn, which correspond to
poion
in the Second Letter.
Socrates in his speech praises Agathon’s approach, yet
shows him that he went all wrong in his praise of Eros. One must first find out
who (what) is the object of the praise, and only then ask of what quality he
(it) is: dei dê (one must), hȏsper su diêgêsȏ (as you have set out),
dielthein auton prȏton (to explain
him first), tis estin ho Erȏs (who is Eros) kai poios tis (and of what quality he is), epeita ta erga autou (and then his
deeds, 201d8-e2). The question ‘who’ (tis)
or ‘what’ (ti) must precede the
question ‘of what quality’.
Let me yet observe that Plato playfully presents
the Symposium in its closing scene both
as a corrective of the Republic and as
its affirmation. In the Republic
Socrates tells Adeimantus: ‘Even when two species of imitation are nearly
allied, the same persons cannot succeed in both, as for example, the writers of
tragedy and comedy – did you not just now call them imitations?’ Adeimantus
replies: ‘Yes, I did; and you are right in thinking tht the same persons cannot
succeed in both.’ (395a3-7, tr. Jowett)
In the closing scene of the Symposium Socrates compelled Agathon and Aristophanes ‘to
acknowledge that the genius of comedy was the same with that of tragedy, and
that the true artist in tragedy was an artist in comedy also. To this they were
constrained to assent, being drowsy, and not quite following the argument. And
first of all Aristophanes dropped off, then, when the day was already dawning,
Agathon. Socrates, having laid them to sleep, rose to depart. At the Lyceum he
took a bath, and passed the day as usual. In the evening he retired to rest at
his own home.’ (223d3-12, tr. Jowett) Here Plato dramatizes the tripartite soul
of the Republic (435a-441c): comedy
appeals to desires, epithumiai, the
lowest part of the soul – Aristophanes, a writer of comedies, is the first to
fall asleep; tragedy appeals to passions, thumos,
which is the intermediary part of the soul – Agathon, a writer of tragedies, is
the next to fall asleep; intellect, nous,
is the highest part of the soul – Socrates, a philosopher, is the only one who
remains waking, leaves the party, and spends his day in Lyceum discussing
philosophy as usual.
No comments:
Post a Comment