Concerning the infinite multitude of Forms
Parmenides says to Socrates: ‘I think that the reason why
you think that each Form is one is like this (Oimai se ek tou toioude hen hekaston eidos oiesthai einai): When many
things appear to you to be large (hotan
poll’ atta megala soi doxêi einai), there perhaps seems to
be some Form, which is one and the same (mia
tis isȏs dokei idea hê autê
einai), as you look on them all (epi
panta idonti); whence (hothen) you
believe the large is one (hen to mega hêgêi
einai)’. Socrates: ‘True (Alêthê
legeis)’. Parmenides: ‘And what about the large itself (Ti d’ auto to mega) and all the other
large things (kai t’alla ta megala),
if in the same way (ean hȏsautȏs)
you look in your mind at all of them (têi psuchêi
epi panta idêis), will not again some
large appear (ouchi hen ti au mega
phaneitai) by which they all appear large (hȏi tauta panta megala
phainesthai)?’ Socrates: ‘It seems so (Eoike)’.
Parmenides: ‘So another Form of largeness (Allo
ara eidos megethous) will come to view (anaphanêsetai), produced alongside the
largeness itself (par’ auto te to
megethos gegonos) and the things participating in it (kai ta metechonta autou); and over and above all these (kai epi toutois pasin), again (au), a different one (heteron), by which they all will be
large (hȏi
tauta panta megala estai). And so you won’t have one of each Form (kai ouketi dê
hen hekaston soi tȏn
eidȏn estai), but their
multitude will be infinite (alla apeira
to plêthos).’ (132a1-b2)
***
Aristotle says in Metaphysics
A: ‘But as for those who posit the Ideas (hoi
de tas ideas tithemenoi), firstly, in seeking to grasp the causes of the
things around us (prȏton men zêtountes tȏnde tȏn ontȏn labein tas
aitias), they introduced others equal in number to these (hetera toutois isa ton artithmon ekomisan),
as if a man who wanted to count things (hȏsper ei tis arithmein boulomenos) thought
he would not be able to do it while they were few (elattonȏn
men ontȏn oioito mê dunêsesthai),
but tried to count them when he had added to their number (pleiȏ de poiêsas arithmoiê)
(990a34-b4) … of the more accurate arguments (hoi de akribesteroi tȏn
logȏn), some lead to Ideas of
relations (hoi men tȏn pros ti poiousi ideas), of which
we say there is no independent class (hȏn ou phamen einai kath’ hauto genos),
and others introduce the ‘third man’ (hoi
de ton triton anthrȏpon
legousi) (b15-17) … and if the Ideas and the particulars that share in them
have the same form (kai ei men t’auto eidos tȏn
ideȏn kai tȏn metechontȏn),
there will be something common to these (estai
ti koinon) … But if they have not the same form (ei de mê
to auto eidos), they must have only the name in common (homȏnuma
an eiê), and it is as if one
were to call both Callias and a wooden image a ‘man’ (kai homoion hȏsper
an ei tis kaloi anthrȏpon
ton te Kallian kai to xulon), without observing any community between them (mêdemian
koinȏnian epiblepsas autȏn)’ (991a2-8, tr. W. D. Ross).
A fragment from Aristotle’s De Ideis elucidates the ‘third man argument’: ‘There will be a
third man (tritos anthrȏpos estai) both apart from each
individual man (para te ton kath’ hekasta),
such as Socrates and Plato (hoion Sȏkratê
kai Platȏna), and apart from the
Form (kai para tên
idean), which is itself one in number (hêtis kai autê
mia kat’ arithmon esti).’ (Alexander of Aphrodisias, in Metaph. 83, W. D. Ross, Aristotelis
fragmenta selecta, Oxford University Press 1955 (1970), p. 125.)
No comments:
Post a Comment