In
‘Self-knowledge as an imperative with comments by David Parker’’ (on my
website) I write: ‘When we become aware of the profound discrepancy between our
physical brain and the world of our consciousness, we realize that there must
be another entity, different from the brain, which transforms the data
processed in the brain into the world of our consciousness … Since our brain
with all its neurons is located in the skull, this entity must also be located
in the skull, for only thus it can transform the data processed by the brain
into the world of our consciousness. The nature of this entity, composed as it
is of a subconscious and conscious part, must be fundamentally different from
the nature of the brain, for the world we are conscious of is not interfered
with by the physical processes in the brain, by the electrical currents and
chemical transmitters generated by neurons.’
David
replies: But how do we know that it isn’t? Again, an
example. Running a marathon is not explained by the molecular events associated
with the actin and myosin fibrils in a muscle, changes in calcium etc.. in a
single or even 100 muscle fibres. But running a marathon is due to, amongst
other things that drive you to run it, activity in large numbers of muscle
cells, together with a skeleton, tendons, ligaments, joint forces that result
from the musculo-skeletal system etc…
I wrongly expected
that the word ‘interfere’ would prevent misunderstanding. So let me give
examples of ‘interference’, which I have in mind, in contrast to ‘influence’
David speaks of. Chemical neurotransmitters, which are produced in the pre-synaptic
cell, are stored in synaptic vesicle; these, are acted on by the action
potentials; released into synaptic clefts, neurotransmitters act on the
receptors in the post-synaptic neuron …
None of this
enters my consciousness, although nothing of what I am conscious of, as I am
typing these lines, takes place without all those activities that take place in
my brain, and influence my consciousness through the intervention of my
subconscious. Conversely, the keyboard on which my eyes are fixed as I am
typing, the computer monitor on which I glance from time to time to check what
I have written – none of it ‘interferes with’ the action potentials and
neurotransmitters in the brain, for it has no place among those activities, although
a great amount of neural activities in different nerve centres in my brain (in visual
cortex, auditory cortex, somatosensory cortex, motor cortex) are influenced by
my seeing the keys, their shapes and their black colour contrasted with the
white colour and the shapes of the letters, by my seeing and moving my fingers,
by my hearing the sound of the keys as I press them …
David
continued: … Why shouldn’t there be consciousness from
the integrated activity processed to a high level in the brain (and this does
not need to be any specific site, it could be distributed).
I continued: ‘It follows as
a matter of course that this entity cannot be interfered with, detected or
manipulated by any physical instruments by means of which science detects
physical phenomena in the brain.’
David remarked: Again, why not. We
cannot find the site of consciousness, despite various sites (cingulate gyrus,
claustrum etc…) being given this role. This could be due to two reasons: there
is no one site but it emerges from the activity of several sites; we simply
lack the technology to detect it. It is not long ago that neuroscience did not
know how neurons signalled within themselves (action potentials) or to other
cells (synapses). These events occurred for millennia even though we have only
detected them in the last 80 years or so.
Aristotle may
help; he notes that topos (place/space)
has three dimensions (diastêmata echei
tria), length (mêkos), breadth (platos) and depth (bathos), by which all body is defined (hois horizetai sôma pan). This might suggest that topos is a body, and so he says: ‘But
the place cannot be body (adunaton de sôma
einai ton topon); for if it were, there would be two bodies in the same
place (en t’autôi gar an eiê duo sômata)’
(Physics, 209a6-7, tr. Hardie and
Gaye). ’Two bodies cannot be at one and the same place’ (duo sômata adunaton hama einai, 213b20)
Everything that
neurophysiology has so far detected and can ever detect in the brain by the technology
corresponds to Aristotle’s notion of body: where is neuron A, there cannot be neuron
B, where is a vesicle A containing neurotransmitter ‘a’, there cannot be a vesicle
B containing the same (or different) kind of neurotransmitter. Concerning action
potentials, let me take recourse to Wikipedia: ‘The action potential generated at the axon hillock propagates as a wave
along the axon … The currents flowing in due to an action potential
spread out in both directions along the axon. However, only the unfired part of the
axon can respond with an action potential; the part that has just fired is
unresponsive until the action potential is safely out of range and cannot re-stimulate
that part.’
I am going to type ‘I’. There must be at
least one neuron that is activated by my seeing the letter ‘I’ on the keyboard,
let it be neuron A. My finger presses the key ‘I’. There must be at least one
neuron B in the motor section of the cortex, which is activated as I press the
key. Let us presume that the axon of neuron A, outstretched to neuron B, activates
neuron B. Neuron A and neuron B are located in the visual and motor cortex
respectively; they interact via the axon of A without changing their places. But
when I type letter ‘I’, my seeing the key and my pressing the key get united in
the space of my mind, which can be viewed as the Kantian space (see ‘The
Kantian subjectivity of space and time’, June 14 , and ‘Kant’s space contrasted
with Aristotle’s space’, July 4). The Kantian space of mind is toto caelo different from the
Aristotelian topos of the brain; only
the latter can be accessed and studied by virtue of technology.
No comments:
Post a Comment