In ‘Celebrating with Homer’ I invited you to my
celebration of the 35th anniversary of the visit of the Master of
Balliol to my philosophy seminar in Prague. The online celebration will go on until
October. In October 15, 1980 the Czechoslovak Communist Party cultural weekly Tvorba published an article ‘How a
campaign of provocation is produced’, which was devoted to the involvement of
Oxford dons in my philosophy seminar. The article opens with a clarion call:
‘The necessity for international cooperation, the exchange
of scientific knowledge, and dialogue are generally acknowledged by honest
and respectable scientists throughout the world. This constitutes an important
part of the endeavour to maintain and strengthen peace around the world. In
the spirit of the stimuli provided by the Final Act at Helsinki, the scope for
cooperation and the exchange of knowledge grows and intensifies even in the
social sciences. The steadily increasing importance of scientific contact is
expressed and actively endorsed by representative forums in the social
sciences; and the stream of world congresses of philosophers, sociologists,
political scientists, economists and historians has convincingly shown the
advantages of this present dialogue.’
But then: ‘Side by side with this undoubtedly fruitful and
beneficial policy, which is the only policy possible for the future, we have
been confronted with the efforts of militant anti-communist forces to stop,
prevent and reverse this hitherto positive development. In the last two years a
provocative action against the Czechoslovak Republic, artificially raked around
the so-called “Tomin case”, acquired such a character. Some people actually
began to hunt after “protests” against the actions of the Czechoslovak
authorities; without asking a single question and without establishing the true
state of affairs they began to defend our “colleague philosopher” Tomin.’
The authors of the article Kořínek and Pulcman don’t say a
word concerning the reasons for the “protests” and for defending “our colleague
philosopher” Tomin. So let me quote a few lines from my article ‘Inside the
Security State’ published in the New Statesman
on May 16, 1980:
‘When I go out of the door of our flat I bump into the Security
[two policemen in uniform; after the Communist takeover of 1948 the police were called ‘bezpečnost’, security, to emphasize their new, people-friendly role].
Four months ago members of the Security carried a table and two chairs into the
third floor of the house in which we live, right in front of our door. Against
our will, two of them stay there twenty-four hours a day, in four-hour shifts.
The Security does not interfere in our flat but its presence outside the doors
has changed everything within. I start to play with my ten-year-old son Marek,
but only because I forget for a while about Security. The moment I realize that
they are outside the door through which every word is heard, let alone shouts
and laughter, we stop. I like to sing – but I don’t sing well. I used to sing
when no-one was at home. I start to sing – then I realize that the Security is
outside and stop singing. My wife and I start talking but inevitably, the ears
of the Security intrude. Our words sound artificial. We become unwilling actors in
front of an unwanted audience. The possibility of being alone with each other
and therefore of being ourselves is taken away from us.’
But back to the Tvorba
article: ‘Some English, French, American, and West German bourgeois
philosophers began to write up protests and even to put pressure upon the
President of the International Association of Philosophical Sicieties (FISP), Professor A. Diemer, to “interfere”. But it sufficed for the president of this
international association to do the most natural thing, viz. to inform himself
by asking the representatives of Czechoslovak philosophy – and the bubble of
the “Tomin case”, blown up to monstrous dimensions, immediately burst.’
The article follows a Letter from Professor Radovan Richta,
Director of the Institute for Philosophy and Sociology, to Professor A. Diemer,
from which I quote: ‘Tomin is worth nothing in philosophy. It is self-evident
that Mr Tomin would not find the means to live for a single week if he were
interesting merely for what he did in philosophy. I think that the people who
supported and visited Mr Tomin will find themselves convinced, in a short time
and on the basis of their own experience, that there has been no case of
“suppression of philosophers in the Czechoslovak Republic”, but rather that it
was a case of one person who wanted to profit from the hopes of some circles to
intensify the world crisis and to poison efforts at international cooperation.’
Let me end this post with another quotation from my article
‘Inside the Security State’:
‘Plato gave mankind a vision of the philosopher-ruler. It is
based on fairly simple concepts: power which is not guided by knowledge is
blind and destructive; it can be of no real use to anyone who does not
understand the meaning of a virtuous life; it will destroy the society which is
ruled by it, destroy those close to the ruler and, above all, it will destroy
the ruler himself. Only the knowledge of Good and Truth enables one to return
power to its rightful place, to change it from a purely destructive force into
an instrument for forging a well-ordered society and the means of achieving a
virtuous and happy life. The correct perception and use of power requires
knowledge. It is therefore knowledge which bestows the right to govern.
Although there are many differences in content (Plato saw
reality only in what is immutable and Ideal; Marx only in what is historical
and material) Platonism does have something in common with Marxism. Marx
perceived that capitalist society, created by the free play of economic forces,
contains within itself the elements of its own destruction. The production of
goods, which should merely fulfil the needs of material existence, has become
an end in itself, man becoming merely the means for creation of an abstract
value – capital. It is necessary radically to change the world, and the key to
such a revolutionary change is a true theory of reality and its dynamics.
Marxism discovers the motive force of revolution – the proletariat – and unites
with it. After the revolution Marxism
provides legitimation for the most developed representatives of the victorious
proletariat to rule the society. Just as in Plato’s ideal state, the possession
of proper theory authorises those who will rule and govern.
As attempts to gain knowledge about the world, Platonism and
Marxism are poles apart in content. So, what could be the meaning of that small
agreement in form: that the correct view of the world – the scientific
world-view – gives the right to govern?
An answer comes to mind. Just as Plato found it necessary to
exclude from the community of his Republic the artist, the fashion-monger and
the purveyor of unacceptable myths, so, in pursuit of Marx’s vision of
communism as the liberation of all creative forces, it became necessary for the
authorized vanguard of the working class – the Communist Party – to exclude
from participation in government all those who, because of their class origin,
were unqualified to direct the society.
Especially dangerous were those who paid lip-service to
Marxism, but in reality tried to revise it and dilute it with divisive foreign
elements. It soon became apparent that new and spontaneous forms of cultural
expression, beginning with dress and hair-style and ending with poetry, song
and dance, were especially dangerous for the journey of the people towards
communism.
As it was very difficult to recognise who was a true
Marxist, it was necessary to find a simple, accessible, and practical
criterion. In Marx’s attempt to find a theory which would enable man to change
the world and to create conditions for his own full development within a
framework of free interpersonal relations, the destruction of all forms of idealism
played a central role.
Crucial above all was the unmasking of the true nature of
religion – ‘the opium of the people’ – which inculcated passive resignation in
the face of poverty, repression, lawlessness and bondage. So faith in God,
belief in the after-life, the burden of idealism – these were the issues on
which people could be examined during interviews in the course of vetting.
It was possible to see with one’s own eyes who still went to
church; it was possible to hear with one’s own ears, among neighbours, friends
and even family, whether those who stopped going to church had really departed
from their misguided beliefs and prejudices and whether their conversion to the
scientific world-view was complete.
The problem of good government is a pressing one today, but
I do not want philosophy to provide me with a solution, or credentials to be a
ruler and so to propagate the Platonic “Noble Lie”. I see in philosophy the
possibility of living freely, but when I speak about living freely I don’t mean
some absolute freedom, but simply freedom within the framework of law. I should
be able to speak as I think, and to act as I feel is correct. I should be able
to relate responsibly to my words and actions, and not to have to disguise
them. Confronted with power I should not have to produce some other persona,
some other face, some other morality. I do not think one can do so with
impunity. I do not believe one can maintain two faces without losing inner
unity. One cannot “lie” face-to-face with power – even if “they don’t deserve
anything better” – without one’s inner truth suffering. Philosophy which
becomes the base of a free life poses a problem for the state power – how to
rule free people. Charter 77 [a petition that asked the Czechoslovak government
to respect basic human rights] has turned this dilemma into a problem which
encompasses the whole society and which is beyond the capacities of the present
power in this state to solve. To resolve this difficulty the power would have
to change internally.
However, instead of this necessary inner change the power
ostentatiously flaunts its repressive mechanisms. It economises on medicines,
on children’s clothing and on pensions but, when it comes to curbing the
activity of people trying to live a little freely, it spares neither expense
nor effort. When it does not succeed in destroying one’s integrity by external
limitations, it seeks to undermine it from inside.
The security outside our doors is not merely an external
restriction of our freedom against which one can successfully build an inner
freedom. The Security controlling all our visitors penetrates into our
relationships with other people and into the most intimate recesses of our own
lives. Is it possible in such a situation to maintain the search for a philosophy
which would give one the strength to live freely in this society? With every
freely said word and with each freely taken step we invite each other to a free
life – with all the implications that the refusal of such an invitation has for
every one of us. Can we, in the given conditions, relate to each other
responsibly and at the same time invite one another to a free existence?’
I wrote the article in Czech in December 1979 and
distributed a copy to a few friends, mostly Charter 77 signatories. The next
day the Security disappeared from our house. It was one of my greatest
victories.
Dr Kathleen Wilkes (she was the first from Oxford that gave a
talk in my philosophy seminar, in April 1979) visited me in Prague in May 1980.
On that occasion she asked me why Petr Pithart, a prominent signatory of the
Charter 77, organised a petition among signatories against the publication of
my article ‘Inside the Security State’; it was signed by 60 of them, Kathy told
me. I replied: ‘Ask Petr Pithart.’ I do not know whether she did so; we never
discussed the issue again.
The Petition did not prevent the publication of the article
in the New Statesman, but it appears to
have exercised its influence. When a Dutch journal wanted to publish it – it
was already translated into Dutch – the Editor of the New Statesman refused to give permission for its publication. I
learnt this from the Editor. He told me while donating to me Julien Benda’s La Trahison des Clercs (The Betrayal of the Intellectuals).
Coincidentally, Alan Montefiore, one of the Oxford dons who had visited my seminar
in 1979, asked me: ‘Do you think we have betrayed you?’ I answered: ‘How could
you betray me? It is you whom you have betrayed.’
As the Tvorba
article said, Professor Richta wrote to Professor Diemer, and the bubble of the
“Tomin case” immediately burst. Or was it more complicated? It was, as my
blog post of November 18, 2014 “The 25th anniversary of Nick Cohen’s
‘The Pub Philosopher’” indicates.
Petr Pithart became the Prime Minister of the Czechoslovak
Republic in February 1990 in the wake of the Velvet Revolution that took place
in November-December 1989.
No comments:
Post a Comment