Kathy Wilkes visited Prague later in May. She was interested
in what happened when Dr Kenny, the Master of Balliol, visited my seminar. It
was on that occasion that it occurred to me that the ancient story might be
true according to which the Phaedrus
was Plato’s first dialogue. The moment I expressed the thought I became aware
of its significance, but I had no idea at that moment that my whole subsequent
life would be influenced by it, for it would put me at loggerheads with the
entire Platonic scholarship as it developed throughout the 19th and
20th centuries. Let me quote Barry O’Brien’s ‘Philosophers in knots
over Dr Tomin’s Plato thesis’ published in The
Daily Telegraph of August 25, 1988: ‘A leading scholar responded yesterday
to complaints by Dr Julius Tomin, the Czech dissident philosopher, that he
cannot get his controversial work on Plato published in Britain.’ The scholar
referred to was Dr David Sedley, editor of Classical
Quarterly and director of studies in classics at Christ’s Church College,
Cambridge. Barry O’Brian says: ‘If Dr Tomin were right, it would affect a great
deal of Platonic scholarship,’ quoting Dr Sedley: “I think people just have a
great difficulty in seeing how it can be right. It means he is asking people to
give up nearly everything else they believe about Plato’s development, but he
is not telling us enough about why we should give up all these other views.” – Dr
Sedley would not publish my views on the dating of the Phaedrus because I was not telling my colleagues enough about why I
thought it was Plato’s first dialogue, and I could not tell my colleagues why I
thought it was Plato’s first dialogue because I was not allowed to present a
paper on the subject to my colleagues, let alone to have my views published. To
cheer me up, an Oxford don donated to me Joseph Heller’s Catch-22.
I described Kenny’s visit in ‘Pursuit of Philosophy’ which I
have put on my website. It was published in the History of Political Thought in 1984. I shall use it to refresh my
memory.
The Master of Balliol arrived at our apartment about half an
hour before the actual beginning of the seminar. He told me that he would be
talking about the pursuit of happiness as it is discussed in Aristotle’s Nicomachean and the Eudemian Ethics. He asked me to translate Nicomachean Ethics 1177a12-6 and Eudemian Ethics 1218b31-1219a39 for my students at the beginning of
the seminar, for in his talk he would refer to these two passages. My text of
the Nicomachean Ethics was heavily
underlined and marked with exclamation marks; though I had not read it for
three or four years, I was confident I could manage. But I never read the Eudemian Ethics, and so I left Kenny and
his wife in care of my wife and went to the kitchen to read the Eudemian text. I just read it once when
my wife summoned me to open the seminar: ‘The living room is packed with
people.’ Kenny opened the seminar by asking me: ‘Julius, would you translate Aristotle’s
Nicomachean Ethics 1177a12-6 and Eudemian Ethics 1218b31-1219a39 for your
students? For I will refer to these two passeges in my talk.’ I replied: ‘I
shall read each sentence aloud in the original and then translate it in Czech.’
When I finished translating, Dr Kenny argued that in the Nicomachean passage happiness consists
in the contemplative activity and philosophy becomes thus the primary source of
happiness, whereas in the Eudemian Ethics
philosophy is one of the optional activities, which only those should pursue
who are called upon to do so. Kenny argued that the Eudemian conception was critical of the Nicomachean conception. If a person organized his life with a view
to the promotion of philosophical speculation without being called upon to do
so he would be not wise but cunning, not phronimos
but panourgos. ‘The type of person
whom many regard as the hero of the Nicomachean
Ethics turns out, by the standards of the Eudemian Ethics, to be a vicious and ignoble character,’ Kenny
maintained. ‘In the Eudemian Ethics happiness
consists of an ideal functioning of every part of the soul,’ he said.
At this point I exchanged the role of an interpreter for the
role of a discussion partner: ‘In the Nicomachean
Ethics Aristotle considers the life in philosophy to be the source of
happiness because the activity of intellect is the highest one. Why should I
see it opposed to the ideal functioning of the other parts of the soul in the Eudemian Ethics? May not Aristotle be
pointing in the direction of the theory fully developed in the tenth book of
the Nicomachean Ethics when he says
in our Eudemian passage: ‘The End (telos) is the best as being an End,
since it is assumed as being the best and ultimate, for the sake of which all
the other things exist’? (1219a10-11). In the Nicomachean Ethics Aristotle says that philosophy is the ultimate
source of good life for it is independent of external circumstances. Even if
deprived of exchanging ideas with his colleagues (sunergoi) he may do philosophy (1177a12-b1). This is especially
important for us in Prague who may face imprisonment any day. It further
reminds me of Socrates. In the Apology he says: “as long as I am able to I will
not stop doing philosophy (29d).” In prison, he transformed his last day into
the best day of his life by discussing philosophy with his friends. Phaedo
opens his narrative of Socrates’ last day by remarking that he could not feel
sorry for Socrates, as one would be expected to be at the approaching death of
a good friend, ‘for the man appeared to me to be happy’ (eudaimȏn gar moi hanêr ephaineto, Phaedo 58e3), and Socrates compares himself to swans who sing most
beautifully and rejoice most on their last day (85b).’
Kenny did not oppose my ‘Socratic’ interpretation of the Nicomachean passage. He questioned
instead the philosophic credentials of Socrates: ‘Julius, wouldn’t you consider
Plato a much better philosopher?’ I replied: ‘Tony, you obviously make such a
cut through Plato’s dialogues that you find Socrates only in dialogues, which
you find unworthy of being called philosophy, and Plato in dialogues which you
find worthy of it. I do not make any such cut through Plato’s dialogues.’
At this point I told Kathy: ‘I’ve suddenly realised that in I
have found nothing in Plato’s dialogues that would compel me to reject Diogenes
Laertius’ story that the Phaedrus was
Plato’s first dialogues.’ (III. 38) – Kathy exclaimed: ‘It can’t be his first
dialogue.’
No comments:
Post a Comment