Plato dramatically staged the Parmenides so as to direct the minds of his disciples to the Republic and thus arm them against any
criticism of the Forms (see the entry of January 10 2015 ‘Plato’s defence of
the Forms in the Parmenides’). Aristotle’s
passionate plea against the theory of Forms in the 9th chapter of
the 1st book of Metaphysics
indicates that Plato’s defence of the Forms in the Parmenides had a profound effect on his disciples: ‘Although
philosophy on the whole seeks the cause of perceptible things (holȏs de
zêtousês tês sophias peri tȏn phanerȏn to aition),
we have given this up (for we say nothing about the cause from which change
takes its start); we think that we are stating the substance of perceptible
things when in fact we state the existence of other substances, while our
account of the way in which they are the substances of perceptible things (hopȏs
d’ ekeinai toutȏn
ousiai) is empty talk (dia kenês legomen); for ‘sharing’ means
nothing (to gar metechein outhen estin),
as we said before’ (992a24-29).
In his response to the Parmenides,
Aristotle too refers to the Republic:
‘Nor have the Forms any connection with what we claim to be the cause in the
case of the sciences (hoper tais
epistêmais horȏmen on aition), that for whose
sake both all mind and the whole of nature are operative, with this cause which
we assert to be one of the first principles; but mathematics has come to be
identical with philosophy for the thinkers of today, though they say that it
should be studied for the sake of other things (992a29-b1).’ Ross in his
commentary rightly notes that Aristotle here refers to the Republic, where Plato views mathematics as a propaedeutic to
philosophy (cf. Rep 533B-E; see Ross’
note ad Met. 992a33).
Concerning the words ‘what we claim to be the cause in the
case of the sciences’ (hoper tais epistêmais
horȏmen on aition) Ross says
that ‘Difficulty has been felt about this, since science is concerned even more
essentially with the formal than the final cause (note on 992a29)’. This
difficulty disappears if we realize that in support of his own position
Aristotle refers to Plato’s Republic.
In the 6th book of the Republic
Plato wrote that ‘the good is the cause of knowledge to all things known’ (tois gignȏskomenois
to gignȏskesthai hupo tou agathou
pareinai, 509b6-8).’
Aristotle’s criticism of the theory of Forms in the 1st
book of Metaphysics is uncompromising:
‘Those who posit the Ideas (hoi de tas
ideas tithemenoi) as causes, firstly, in seeking to grasp the causes of
things around us, they introduced others equal in number to these, as if a man
who wanted to count things thought he would not be able to do it while they
were few, but tried to count them when he had added to their number (990a34-b4)
… Further, of the ways in which we prove that the Forms exist, none is
convincing; for from some no inference necessarily follows, and from some arise
Forms even of things of which we think there are no Forms (990b9-11) … Above
all one might discuss the question what on earth the Forms contribute to
sensible things, either to those that are eternal [i. e. the heavenly bodies –
W. D. Ross’ note ad 991a9] or to those that come into being and cease to be.
For they cause neither movement nor any change in them. But again they help in
no wise either towards the knowledge of the other things (for they are not even
the substance of these, else they would have been in them), or towards their
being, if they are not in the particulars which share in them’ (991a8-14, tr.
Ross).
But Plato in the Parmenides
gave voice to, dramatically displayed and enhanced the difficulties in which
the theory of Forms is entangled, in particularly the difficulties involved in
the theory of participation of perceptible things in the Forms and difficulties
concerning the contribution the Forms can possibly make to our knowledge of
things around us (133b-134e). Plato not only conceived the Forms face to face
with all this criticism of the theory, criticism of which he was well aware
from the time he became interested in philosophy, but steadfastly adhered to
them – this is what the Parmenides is
all about. How was this possible? The answer lies in the way in which Plato
conceived the Forms, as Aristotle explains it in Metaphysics A.
Aristotle says that Plato in his
youth embraced the Heraclitean doctrines ‘that all things are in constant flux
(hȏs
hapantȏn aei reontȏn) and there is no knowledge about
them’ (kai epistêmês peri autȏn
ouk ousês, 987a33-34). To
understand the significance of this statement, we must pay due attention to the
Greek concept of knowledge. Epistêmê signifies
‘standing on’; it is derived from ephistêmi,
‘stop, cause to halt’. Aristotle says in the Physics: ‘for it is when the mind has reached a state of rest and
come to a standstill (tȏi gar êremêsai
kai stênai tên dianoian) that we say we know and understand (epistasthai kai phronein legometha,
247b11-12)’. Engrossed in the Heraclitean view of reality, Plato encountered
Socrates ‘who was the first to have stopped and fixed his mind on definitions
of ethical concepts’ (peri horismȏn epistêsantos
prȏtou tên dianoian, Met A,
987b3-4); Plato realized ‘that the entities on which mind could be thus fixed
and brought to a standstill were different from perceptible things (hȏs peri heterȏn touto gignomenon kai ou tȏn
aisthêtȏn). He called the entities of this kind Forms’ (houtos men oun ta men toiauta tȏn ontȏn
ideas prosêgoreuse, 987b5-8).
Plato did not conceive the Forms on
the basis of observations concerning things around him as young Socrates did in
the Parmenides and as did Plato’s
disciples at whom Aristotle directed his criticism. On his encounter with Socrates,
Plato saw the Forms with his soul’s eye (cf. to tês psuchês omma, Rep.
533d2). After Plato had conceived the Forms, his Heraclitean view of the
perceptible world remained unchanged: ‘this view he held even later’ (tauta men kai husteron houtȏs hupelaben, Met. A 987a34-b1), that is after he had conceived the Forms. In the
Republic Plato insists that there can
be no knowledge concerning things perceived by the senses (508d-511e); this is
why his view of the Forms was immune to Aristotelian arguments against the
Forms.
Face to face with the Parmenides Aristotle was well aware that
his arguments against the Forms were powerless against Plato’s view of the
Forms; he directed his arguments against the Forms at those, who like himself
believed that ‘philosophy on the whole seeks the cause of perceptible
things’ (holȏs
de zêtousês tês sophias peri tȏn phanerȏn to aition, Met. A 992a24-25).
No comments:
Post a Comment