Sorabji’s
fourth objection against my dating of Plato’ Phaedrus: ‘There is a right way of teaching Rhetoric according to
the Phaedrus, but it must be combined
with Psychology. I had previously accepted the view (Jaeger’s?) that Aristotle
put this into practice in his Rhetoric,
of which Book II is in large part a psychological study. Both his Rhetoric and (on this view) Plato Phaedrus would then come later than the
unqualified denunciation of Rhetoric in the Gorgias.
Does Diogenes Laertius’s different order make equally good sense?’
***
In the
preceding post I discussed Hackforth’s note: ‘We may believe that it is a
reformed rhetoric that is allotted an honourable function in the state at Pol. 304 D: kai toûto men eoike tachu kechôristhai politikês to rêtorikon, hôs
heteron ei͒dos on, hupêretoûn mên tautê̢ (‘Rhetoric seems to be quickly
distinguished from politics, being a different species, yet ministering to it’,
tr. B. Jowett).’ (R. Hackforth, Plato’s
Phaedrus, Cambridge at the University Press, 1972, p. 11) I argued that the
reformed rhetoric of the Phaedrus is based
on dialectic, i.e. on philosophy, and it serves no external master, whereas the
rhetoric in the Statesman is
subservient to the Statesman.
I wrote that
an implicit unity between the philosopher, the politician, and the master of
the reformed rhetoric underlies the discussion of the reformed rhetoric in the Phaedrus. To corroborate this statement,
I quoted a substantial part of Socrates’ imaginary discussion with the
rhetorician Tisias. But when I think about that discussion more attentively, I
must improve on the statement I had made. For in the light of that discussion only
a philosopher can master the reformed rhetoric; he can use the reformed
rhetoric for political aims, if he wishes to, and nobody can be a better
politician than he; but his real aims, the aims for the sake of which he mastered
rhetoric based on dialectic are much higher. In other words, the science
mastered by the true rhetorician is much higher than the art of the statesman.
In the Statesman it is quite the
opposite; the science of the Statesman governs rhetoric, the art of persuasion,
and is far superior to it.
In fact,
Plato in the Statesman speaks of
rhetoric in pejorative terms, which is reminiscent of the Euthydemus. If we take this fully on board, we realize that there
is hardly any ground for the reformed rhetoric of the Phaedrus anywhere between the Euthydemus
and the Statesman. What links these
two dialogues in the first place, in so far as they speak of rhetoric, is the
pejorative term ochlos ‘mob’,
‘popular assembly’ (in contemptuous sense, as L&S remarks). In the Statesman the Eleatic Stranger asks: ‘To
what science do we assign the power of persuading (tini to peistikon ou͒n apodôsomen epistêmê̢) a multitude and a
mob (plêthous te kai ochlou) by
telling tales (dia muthologias) and
not by teaching (alla mê dia didachês)?’
– Young Socrates answers: ‘That power, I think, must clearly be assigned to
rhetoric (Phaneron oi͒mai kai toûto
rêtorikê̢ doteon on).’ (Pol.
304c10-d3) In the Euthydemus Socrates
defines rhetoric (tên logopoiikên
technên, ‘the art of making speeches’, 289c7) as ‘the bewitching and
calming down judges and men in the assembly and the other mobs (hê dikastôn te kai ekklêsiastôn kai tôn
allôn ochlôn kêlêsis, 290a3-4).’
There are other
parallels between these two dialogues. In the Euthydemus Socrates tries to define the science/wisdom/knowledge the
possession of which would give us happiness, and weeds out those arts that
falsely aspire to that dignity, thus rejecting any claim of rhetoric to such
status. In the Statesman the Eleatic
Stranger separates rhetoric from the science/art of the Statesman as an art
distinct from it yet subservient to it.
In the Euthydemus Socrates begins with a great
praise of the masters of rhetoric – only to lash them the more severely with
his irony: ‘And yet I did think (kaitoi
egô ô̢mên) that somewhere around here would appear the branch of
knowledge (entautha pou phanêsesthai
tên epistêmên) we’ve been so long seeking (hên dê palai zêtoumen): for the speech-writers themselves (kai gar moi hoi te andres autoi hoi
logopoioi), whenever I am in their company (hotan sungenômai autois), have always appeared to me to be
extraordinarily wise (hupersophoi
dokousin ei͒nai), and their art itself divine and lofty (kai autê hê technê autôn thespesia tis
kai hupsêlê).’ Then comes the irony: ‘And no wonder (kai mentoi ouden thaumaston), it’s a part of the art of enchantment
(esti gar tês tôn epô̢dôn morion)
…’ (Euth. 289e1-5)
In the Statesman the Stranger introduces the
separation of the arts by comparing it to the task of those who are refining
the gold (toîs ton chruson kathairousi,
303d6-7): ‘In like manner (Kata ton auton
toinun logon eoike kai nûn hêmîn), all alien and uncongenial matter has
been separated from political science (ta
men hetera kai hoposa allotria kai ta mê phila politikês epistêmês
apokechôristhai), and what is precious and of a kindred nature has been
left (leipesthai de ta timia kai sungenê);
there remain the nobler arts of the general and the judge (toutôn d’ esti pou stratêgia kai dikastikê), and the higher sort
of oratory which is an ally of the royal art (kai hosê basilikê̢ koinônousa rêtoreia), and persuades men to
do justice (peithousa to dikaion),
and assists in guiding the helm of states (sundiakubernâ̢
tas en taîs polesi praxeis): How can we
best clear away all these (ha dê
tini tropô̢ ra̢sta tis apomerizôn), leaving him whom we seek alone and
unalloyed (deixei gumnon kai monon
ekeînon kath’ hauton ton zêtoumenon huph’ hêmôn;)? (303e7-304a4, tr.
Jowett).
How does the
Stranger clear away ‘the higher sort of oratory’ from ‘the royal art’? Stranger:
‘There is such a thing as learning music (Mousikês
esti pou tis hêmîn mathêsis) and handicraft arts in general (kai holôs tôn peri cheirotechnias epistêmôn)?’ – Young Socrates:
‘There is (Estin).’ – Str. ‘And is
there any higher art or science,
having power to decide which of these arts are and are not to be learned (to d’ au toutôn hêntinoun eite deî
manthanein hêmas eite mê, potera phêsomen epistêmên au kai tautên ei͒nai tina peri auta taûta, ê pôs;)?
– Y. Soc. ‘I should answer that there is (Houtôs,
ei͒nai phêsomen).’ – Str. ‘And do we acknowledge this science to be
different from the others (Oukoûn
heteran homologêsomen ekeinôn ei͒nai tautên;)?’ – Y. Soc. ‘Yes (Nai).’ – Str. ‘And ought the other
sciences to be superior to this, or no single science to any other (Potera de autôn oudemian archein deîn
allên allês, ê ekeinas tautês)? Or ought this science to be the
overseer and governor (ê tautên deîn
epitropeuousan archein) of all the others (sumpasôn tôn allôn;)?’ – Y. Soc. ‘The latter (Tautên ekeinôn).’ – Str. ‘You mean to
say that the science which judges whether we ought to learn or not (Tên ei deî manthanein ê mê), must be
superior to the science which is learned or which teaches (tês manthanomenês kai didaskousês ara su ge apophainê̢ deîn
hêmîn archein;)?’ – Y. Soc. ‘Far superior (Sphodra ge).’ – Str. ‘And the science which determines whether we
ought to persuade or not (Kai tên ei
deî peithein ê mê), must be superior to the science which is able to
persuade (tês dunamenês peithein;)?’
– Y. Soc. ‘Of course (Pôs d’ ou;).’ –
Str. `Very good (Eien); and to what science do we assign the power of
persuading (tini to peistikon ou͒n
apodôsomen epistêmê̢) a
multitude (plêthous te kai ochlou ‘a
multitude and mob’) by a pleasing tale (dia
muthologias) and not by teaching (alla
mê dia didachês)?’ – Y. Soc. ‘That power, I think, must clearly be
assigned to rhetoric (Phaneron oi͒mai kai
toûto rêtorikê̢ doteon on).’ (304b1-d3, tr. B. Jowett)
As can be
seen, the mediating function of music and handicraft sciences in general (kai
holôs tôn peri cheirotechnias epistêmôn)
emphasizes the superiority of the political science to rhetoric, the science (epistêmê̢) to which is
assigned ‘the power of persuading a multitude and a mob by tale and not by
teaching’. Note that before refering to rhetoric as science (epistêmê) the Stranger refers to
handicrafts as sciences (epistêmôn).
***
The Euthydemus and the Statesman have in common an important doctrinal aspect: they both
insist that philosophy and politics are different disciplines.
At the end
of the Euthydemus, Crito tells
Socrates that a famous speech-writer, whom he doesn’t name, severely criticised
Socrates for his having been involved in a discussion with Euthydemus and
Dionysodorus, two sophists. Having listened to the criticism, and to Crito’s
characterization of the critic, Socrates says at the address of the latter: ‘He
is one of those (houtoi gar eisi men)
whom Prodicus describes (hous ephê
Prodicos) as on the border-ground between philosophers and statesmen (methoria philosophou te andros kai politikou,
305c6-7) … they have a certain amount of philosophy (metriôs men gar philosophias echein), and a certain amount of
political wisdom (metriôs de politikôn,
305d8) … if philosophy and political action are both good (ei men ou͒n hê philosophia agathon estin kai hê politikê praxis),
but tend to different ends (pros allo de
hekatera), and they participate in both (hoûtoi amphoterôn de metechontes), and are in a mean between them
(toutôn en mesô̢ eisin) … then they are worse than either (amphoterôn eisi phauloteroi, 306b2-5) (305c6-306b5
tr. B. Jowett) … The fact of the matter is (alla
tô̢ onti), that because they have a foot in both camps (houtoi amphoterôn metechontes), they
fail in both (amphoterôn hêttous eisin)
of the respective purposes (pros
hekateron) for which philosophy and statesmanship are worthwhile (pros ho hê te politikê kai hê te
philosophia axiô logou eston, 306c2-4, tr. Robin Waterfield).’
In the Statesman the Stranger undertakes to
define the Statesman as different from the Philosopher; the Sophist, the Statesman, and the Philosopher
were to be a trilogy, but the Philosopher
was never written.
At the
beginning of the Sophist Socrates
asked the Eleatic Stranger what the people in Elea thought of ‘sophist,
statesman, and philosopher (sophistên,
politikon, philosophon), whether they viewed them as terms describing one
and the same kind of person (poteron hen
panta taûta enomizon), or two (ê
duo), or as the names are three (ê
kathaper ta onomata tria), distinguishing three kinds (tria kai ta genê diairoumenoi) they assigned one name to each (kath’ hen onoma hekastô̢ prosêpton,
217a3-8). The Eleatic Stranger answered: ‘They regarded them as three (tri’ hêgounto), but to define the
nature of each clearly (kath’ heakaston
mên diorisasthai saphôs ti pot estin) is not a small (ou smikron) or easy task (oude ra̢dion ergon, 217b2-3).
The Statesman opens with Socrates addressing
Theodorus: ‘I owe you many thanks, indeed, Theodorus, for the acquaintance both
of Theaetetus and of the Stranger (Ê
pollên charin opheilô soi tês Theaitêtou gnôriseôs, ô Theodôre, hama
kai tês toû xenou).’ [Theaetetus, a disciple of Theodorus, was Socrates’
interlocutor in the Theaetetus and in
the Sophist; the Theaetetus ended with a promise to meet the next day; next day
Theodorus brought with him not only Theaetetus, but as well the Eleatic
Stranger, and young Socrates, who becomes the Stranger’s interlocutor in the Statesman.] – Theodorus: ‘And in a
little while (Tacha de), Socrates (ô Sôkrates), you will owe me three
times as many [thanks] (opheilêseis tautês
triplasian), when they have completed to you the delineation of the
Statesman (epeidan ton te politikon
apergasôntai soi) and of the Philosopher (kai ton philosophon).’
(257a1-5) – Theodorus turns to the Stranger: ‘I must now ask the
Stranger (su d’ hêmîn, ô xene) …
to proceed either with the Statesman or with the Philosopher, whichever he
prefers (eite ton politikon andra
proteron eite ton philosophon proairê̢, proelomenos diexelthe, 257257b8-c1).’
– Stranger: ‘That is my duty, Theodorus (Taût’,
ô Theodôre, poiêteon); having begun (epeiper
hapax ge enkecheirêkamen) I must go on (ouk apostateon), and not leave the work unfinished (prin an autôn pros to telos elthômen,
257c2-4) … After the Sophist, then (alla
dê meta ton sophistên), I think that the Statesman naturally follows next
in the order of enquiry (anankaion, hôs
emoi phainetai, politikon ton andra diazêtein nô̢n, 258b2-3).’
(Translation B. Jowett)
It is worth
noting that the Stranger’s ‘the Statesman naturally (anankaion ‘necessarily’) follows next in the order of enquiry’
indicates that the Philosopher stands higher in dignity.
***
The unity of
philosopher and statesman forms the very foundation of Plato’s ideal State in
the Republic: ‘Until
philosophers are the kings in their cities (Ean
mê ê hoi philosophoi basileusôsin en taîs polesin), or the kings and
princes of this world have the spirit and power of philosophy (ê hoi basilês te nûn legomenoi kai
dunastai philosophêsôsi gnêsiôs te kai hikanôs), and political greatness and wisdom meet in one (kai
touto eis t’auton sumpesê̢, dunamis te politikê kai philosophia), and
those commoner natures who pursue either to the exclusion of the other are
compelled to stand aside (tôn de nun
poreuomenôn chôris eph’ hekateron hai pollai phuseis ex anankês
apokleisthôsin), cities will never have rest from their evils (ouk estin kakôn paûla taîs polesi) –
no, nor the human race, as I believe (dokô
d’oude tô̢ anthrôpinô̢ genei).’ (473c11-d6, tr. B. Jowett)
In the Laws Plato presents to
his interlocutors ‘the best state’ outlined in the Republic as the guiding principle for the second-best state: ‘The
first and highest form of the state and of the government and of the law is
that (Prôtê men toinun polis te estin
kai politeia kai nomoi aristoi) in which there prevails most widely the
ancient saying (hopou to palai legomenon
an gignêtai kata pâsan tên polin hoti malista), that “Friends have all
things in common” (legetai de hôs ontôs
esti koina ta tôn philôn). Whether there is anywhere now (tout’ ou͒n eite pou nûn estin), or will
ever be (eit’ estai pote), this
communion of women (koinas men gunaikas)
and children (koinous de einai paidas)
and of property (koina de chrêmata
sumpanta), in which the private and individual is altogether banished from
life (kai pasê̢ mêchanê̢ to legomenon
idion pantachothen ek tou biou hapan exê̢rêtai), and things which are by
nature private, such as eyes and ears and hands, have become common, and in
some way see and hear and act in common (memêchanêtai
d’ eis to dunaton kai ta phusei idia koina hamê̢ ge pê̢ gegonenai, hoion
ommata kai o͒ta kai cheîras koina men horân dokeîn kai akouein kai prattein),
and all men express praise and blame and feel joy and sorrow on the same
occasions (epaineîn t’ au kai psegein
kath’ hen hoti malista sumpantas epi toîs autoîs chairontas kai lupoumenous),
and whatever laws there are unite the city to the utmost (kai kata dunamin hoitines nomoi mian hoti malista polin apergazontai)
– no man, acting upon any other principle, will ever constitute a state which
will be truer or better or more excellent in virtue (toutôn huperbolê̢ pros aretên oudeis pote horon allon themenos
orthoteron oude beltiô thêsetai) … to
this we are to look for the pattern of the state (dio dê paradeigma ge politeias ouk allê̢ chrê skopeîn), and to cling to this (all’ echomenous
tautês), and to seek with all our might
for one which is like this (tên hoti
malista toiautên zêteîn kata dunamin).’ (739b8-e3, tr. B. Jowett)
It is this ideal of unity and community, forcefully expressed in Republic V, 462a2-c10, which leads to
the postulate of political greatness and wisdom meeting in one in Republic V, 473c11-d6, and to necessarily excluding those who pursue the
one or the other separately (tôn de nun
poreuomenôn chôris eph’ hekateron hai pollai phuseis ex anankês apokleisthôsin, 473d3-5). Yet in the Statesman and in the Philosopher Plato undertook the separation
of philosophy and of the art/science of statesmanship.
***
The unity of
statesmanship and philosophy is central to Plato’s ideal State in the Republic, and there is no place in it for
rhetoric; in the Laws, which outlines
the second-best state, is no place for rhetoric either. In contrast, both in the Euthydemus,
which can be safely dated prior to the Republic,
and in the Statesman, which can be
safely dated after it, rhetoric is accepted, yet viewed as deficient both to
philosophy and to statesmanship, regarded as separate disciplines. It thus appears
that on doctrinal grounds there is no place for the reformed rhetoric of the Phaedrus in the period of Plato’s
writings that begins with the Euthydemus
and ends with the Laws.
***
I have now decided to re-read the Statesman
next, for obtaining clarity into the affinity between the Statesman to the Euthydemus
and its difference from the Republic appears
to be of greater importance for the consideration of the dating of the Phaedrus on doctrinal grounds than Aristotle’s
Rhetoric suggested by Sorabji.
***
This does not mean that I dismiss the possibility that Aristotle may
shed light on this matter. Consider the light he sheds on the relationship
between the Republic and the Laws in his Politics: ‘In the Republic,
Socrates has definitely settled in all a few questions only (en tê̢ Politeia̢ peri oligôn pampan
diôriken ho Sôkratês); such as the community of women and children (peri te gunaikôn kai teknôn koinônias,
pôs echein deî), the community of property (kai peri ktêseôs), and the constitution of the state (kai tês politeias tên taxin). The
population is divided into two classes (diaireitai
gar eis duo merê to plêthos tôn oikountôn) – one of husbandmen (to men eis tous geôrgous), and the
other of warriors (to de eis to
propolemoun meros); from this is taken a third class of counsellors and
rulers of state (triton d’ ek
toutôn to bouleuomenon kai kurion tês
poleôs) … In the Laws there is
hardly anything but laws (tôn de Nomôn
to men pleîston meros nomoi
tunchanousin ontes); not much is said about the constitution (oliga de peri tês politeias eirêken).
This, which he had intended to make more of the ordinary type (kai tautên boulomenos koinoteran poieîn
taîs polesi), he gradually brings round to the other ideal form (kata mikron periagei palin pros tên heteran
politeian). For with the exception of the community of women and property (exô gar tês tôn gunaikôn koinônias kai
tês ktêseôs), he supposes everything to be the same in both states (ta alla t’auta apodidôsin amphoterais taîs
politeiais); there is to be the same education (kai gar paideian tên autên); the citizens of both are to live
free from servile occupations (kai to tôn ergôn tôn anankaiôn apechomenous zên), and there are to be common meals
in both (kai peri sussitiôn hôsautôs).’
(Aristotle, Politics 1264b26-1265a8,
tr. B. Jowett. Let me note that Aristotle does not say that ‘the citizens of
both are to live free from servile
occupations’; he says that they are to live free from necessary occupations (tôn
ergôn tôn anankaiôn).
***
In my last but one post (4b1) I wrote that my quick and perfunctory reading of
several chapters of Aristotle’s Rhetoric
compelled me to look more thoroughly at the first few chapters of Book I, that on
that basis I resolved to read Aristotle’s Rhetoric
from alpha to omega, but that Aristotle’s covert references to the Gorgias in the first two chapters made
me realize that I must begin with Plato’s Gorgias.
I read the Gorgias, and then the Euthydemus. The Euthydemus combined with the discussion of rhetoric in the Statesman, to which I was alerted by
Hackforth, made me realise that the next thing I must do is to re-read the Statesman. And now, reading what
Aristotle says on Plato’s Republic
and Laws in his Politics made me realize that if I am to see what can be said about
the dating of the Phaedrus on
doctrinal grounds, then I must re-read not only Plato’s Statesman, but his Laws
as well before Aristotle’s Rhetoric.